Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| ==Notes & Queries== | | ==Notes & Queries== |
− | [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 11:44, 17 May 2007 (PDT) | + | |
| + | # [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 15:34, 8 January 2006 (UTC) |
| + | # [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 11:44, 17 May 2007 (PDT) |
| + | # [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 07:28, 24 January 2008 (PST) |
| + | |
| + | ===Pragmatic theory of inquiry=== |
| + | |
| + | ===Classical models=== |
| + | |
| + | JA: I am dumping some raw source material here until I can sort it out. [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 19:26, 14 April 2006 (UTC) |
| + | |
| + | References: |
| + | |
| + | * [[Aristotle]], "The Categories", [[Harold P. Cooke]] (trans.), pp. 1–109 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938. |
| + | |
| + | * [[Aristotle]], "On Interpretation", [[Harold P. Cooke]] (trans.), pp. 111–179 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938. |
| + | |
| + | * [[Aristotle]], "[[Prior Analytics]]", [[Hugh Tredennick]] (trans.), pp. 181–531 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938. |
| + | |
| + | * [[Aristotle]], "[[On the Soul]]" (''De Anima''), [[W.S. Hett]] (trans.), pp. 1–203 in ''Aristotle, Volume 8'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1936. |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | Appendix A: Sources |
| + | Aristotle: On Interpretation |
| + | Chapter 1 |
| + | |
| + | {1} Words spoken are symbols or signs of affections or impressions |
| + | of the soul; written words are the signs of words spoken. As |
| + | writing, so also is speech not the same for all races of men. |
| + | But the mental affections themselves, of which these words |
| + | are primarily signs, are the same for the whole of mankind, |
| + | as are also the objects of which those affections are |
| + | representations or likenesses, images, copies. |
| + | |
| + | Aristotle: Prior Analytics |
| + | Book 1 Chapter 4 |
| + | {1} When three terms are so related to one another that the last |
| + | is wholly contained in the middle and the middle is wholly |
| + | contained in or excluded from the first, the extremes must admit |
| + | of perfect syllogism. By 'middle term' I mean that which both is |
| + | contained in another and contains another in itself, and which is |
| + | the middle by its position also; and by 'extremes' (a) that which |
| + | is contained in another, and (b) that in which another is |
| + | contained. For if A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, |
| + | A must necessarily be predicated of all C. ... I call this kind |
| + | of figure the First. |
| + | |
| + | Chapter 5 |
| + | |
| + | {2} When the same term applies to all of one subject and to none |
| + | of the other, or to all or none of both, I call this kind of |
| + | figure the Second; and in it by the middle term I mean that which |
| + | is predicated of both subjects; by the extreme terms, the subjects |
| + | of which the middle is predicated; by the major term, that which |
| + | comes next to the middle; and by the minor that which is more |
| + | distant from it. The middle is placed outside the extreme terms, |
| + | and is first by position. |
| + | |
| + | Chapter 6 |
| + | |
| + | {3} If one of the terms applies to all and the other to none of |
| + | the same subject, or if both terms apply to all or none of it, |
| + | I call this kind of figure the Third; and in it by the middle I |
| + | mean that of which both the predications are made; by extremes |
| + | the predicates; by the major term that which is [further from?] |
| + | the middle; and by the minor that which is nearer to it. The |
| + | middle is placed outside the extremes, and is last by position. |
| + | |
| + | Book 2 Chapter 21 |
| + | |
| + | {1} Similarly too with the theory in the Meno that learning is |
| + | recollection. For in no case do we find that we have previous |
| + | knowledge of the individual, but we do find that in the process |
| + | of induction we acquire knowledge of particular things just as |
| + | though we could remember them; for there are some things which we |
| + | know immediately: e.g., if we know that X is a triangle we know |
| + | that the sum of its angles is equal to two right angles. |
| + | Similarly too in all other cases. |
| + | |
| + | {2} Thus whereas we observe particular things by universal |
| + | knowledge, we do not know them by the knowledge peculiar to them. |
| + | Hence it is possible to be mistaken about them, not because we |
| + | have contrary knowledge about them, but because, although we have |
| + | universal knowledge of them, we are mistaken in our particular |
| + | knowledge. |
| + | |
| + | Book 2 Chapter 23 |
| + | |
| + | {1} Induction epagwgh, or inductive reasoning, consists in |
| + | establishing a relation between one extreme term and the middle |
| + | term by means of the other extreme; e.g., if B is the middle term |
| + | of A and C, in proving by means of C that A applies to B; for this |
| + | is how we effect inductions. E.g., let A stand for 'long-lived', |
| + | B for 'that which has no bile' and C for the long-lived |
| + | individuals such as man and horse and mule. Then A applies to the |
| + | whole of C, for every bileless animal is long-lived. But B, 'not |
| + | having bile', also applies to all C. Then if C is convertible |
| + | with B, i.e., if the middle term is not wider in extension, |
| + | A must apply to B. |
| + | |
| + | {2} This kind of syllogism is concerned with the first or |
| + | immediate premiss. Where there is a middle term, the syllogism |
| + | proceeds by means of the middle; where there is not, it proceeds |
| + | by induction. There is a sense in which induction is opposed to |
| + | syllogism, for the latter shows by the middle term that the major |
| + | extreme applies to the third, while the former shows by means of |
| + | the third that the major extreme applies to the middle. Thus by |
| + | nature the syllogism by means of the middle is prior and more |
| + | knowable; but syllogism by induction is more apparent to us. |
| + | |
| + | Book 2 Chapter 24 |
| + | |
| + | {1} We have an Example paradeigma when the major extreme is shown |
| + | to be applicable to the middle term by means of a term similar to |
| + | the third. It must be known both that the middle applies to the |
| + | third term and that the first applies to the term similar to the |
| + | third. E.g., let A be 'bad', B 'to make war on neighbors', |
| + | C 'Athens against Thebes' and D 'Thebes against Phocis'. Then |
| + | if we require to prove that war against Thebes is bad, we must be |
| + | satisfied that war against neighbors is bad. Evidence of this can |
| + | be drawn from similar examples, e.g., that war by Thebes against |
| + | Phocis is bad. Then since war against neighbors is bad, and war |
| + | against Thebes is against neighbors, it is evident that war |
| + | against Thebes is bad. Now it is evident that B applies to C |
| + | and D (for they are both examples of making war on neighbors), |
| + | and A to D (since the war against Phocis did Thebes no good); but |
| + | that A applies to B will be proved by means of D. ... |
| + | |
| + | {2} Thus it is evident that an example represents the relation, |
| + | not of part to whole or of whole to part, but of one part to |
| + | another, where both are subordinate to the same general term, |
| + | and one of them is known. It differs from induction in that the |
| + | latter, as we saw, shows from an examination of all the individual |
| + | cases that the [major] extreme applies to the middle, and does not |
| + | connect the conclusion with the [minor] extreme; whereas the |
| + | example does connect it and does not use all the individual cases |
| + | for its proof. |
| + | |
| + | Book 2 Chapter 25 |
| + | |
| + | {1} We have Reduction apagwgh (a) when it is obvious that the |
| + | first term applies to the middle, but that the middle applies to |
| + | the last term is not obvious, yet nevertheless is more probable or |
| + | not less probable than the conclusion; or (b) if there are not |
| + | many intermediate terms between the last and the middle; for in |
| + | all such cases the effect is to bring us nearer to knowledge. |
| + | |
| + | {2} (a) E.g., let A stand for 'that which can be taught', B for |
| + | 'knowledge' and C for 'morality'. Then that knowledge can be |
| + | taught is evident; but whether virtue is knowledge is not clear. |
| + | Then if BC is not less probable or is more probable than AC, we |
| + | have reduction; for we are nearer to knowledge for having |
| + | introduced an additional term, whereas before we had no knowledge |
| + | that AC is true. |
| + | |
| + | {3} (b) Or again we have reduction if there are not many |
| + | intermediate terms between B and C; for in this case too we are |
| + | brought nearer to knowledge. E.g., suppose that D is 'to square', |
| + | E 'rectilinear figure' and F 'circle'. Assuming that between |
| + | E and F there is only one intermediate term - that the circle |
| + | becomes equal to a rectilinear figure by means of lunules - |
| + | we should approximate to knowledge. |
| + | |
| + | {4} When, however, BC is not more probable than AC, or there are |
| + | several intermediate terms, I do not use the expression |
| + | 'reduction'; nor when the proposition BC is immediate; for such |
| + | a statement implies knowledge. |
| + | |
| + | Book 2 Chapter 27 |
| + | |
| + | {1} A probability eikoV is not the same as a sign shmeion. The |
| + | former is a generally accepted premiss; for that which people know |
| + | to happen or not to happen, or to be or not to be, usually in a |
| + | particular way, is a probability: e.g., that the envious are |
| + | malevolent or that those who are loved are affectionate. A sign, |
| + | however, means a demonstrative premiss which is necessary or |
| + | generally accepted. That which coexists with something else, |
| + | or before or after whose happening something else has happened, |
| + | is a sign of that something's having happened or being. |
| + | |
| + | {2} An enthymeme is a syllogism from probabilities or signs; and |
| + | a sign can be taken in three ways - in just as many ways as there |
| + | are of taking the middle term in the several figures ... |
| + | |
| + | {3} We must either classify signs in this way, and regard their |
| + | middle term as an index tekmhrion (for the name 'index' is given |
| + | to that which causes us to know, and the middle term is especially |
| + | of this nature), or describe the arguments drawn from the extremes |
| + | as 'signs', and that which is drawn from the middle as an 'index'. |
| + | For the conclusion which is reached through the first figure is |
| + | most generally accepted and most true. |
| + | |
| + | Aristotle: The Art of Rhetoric |
| + | |
| + | Book 1 Chapter 2 |
| + | |
| + | {1} But for purposes of demonstration, real or apparent, just as |
| + | Dialectic possesses two modes of argument, induction and the |
| + | syllogism, real or apparent, the same is the case in Rhetoric; |
| + | for the example is induction, and the enthymeme a syllogism, and |
| + | the apparent enthymeme an apparent syllogism. Accordingly I call |
| + | an enthymeme a rhetorical syllogism, and an example rhetorical |
| + | induction. |
| + | |
| + | {2} But since few of the propositions of the rhetorical syllogism |
| + | are necessary, ... it is evident that the materials from which |
| + | enthymemes are derived will be sometimes necessary, but for the |
| + | most part only generally true; and these materials being |
| + | probabilities and signs, it follows that these two elements must |
| + | correspond to these two kinds of propositions, each to each. ... |
| + | </pre> |