Line 117: |
Line 117: |
| 3 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ | | 3 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ |
| 4 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ | | 4 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ |
− | 5 & {}^{\shortparallel} & {}^{\shortparallel} & {}^{\shortparallel} | + | 5 & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel |
| \end{array}</math> | | \end{array}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
Line 134: |
Line 134: |
| 3 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ | | 3 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ |
| 4 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ | | 4 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ |
− | 5 & {}^{\shortparallel} & {}^{\shortparallel} & {}^{\shortparallel} | + | 5 & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel |
| \end{array}</math> | | \end{array}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
Line 1,920: |
Line 1,920: |
| ==Visualization== | | ==Visualization== |
| | | |
− | In my work on [[Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems 2.0|Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems]], I found it useful to develop several different ways of visualizing logical transformations, indeed, I devised four distinct styles of picture for the job. Thus far in our work on the mapping <math>F : [u, v] \to [u, v],\!</math> we've been making use of what I call the ''areal view'' of the extended universe of discourse, <math>[u, v, du, dv],\!</math> but as the number of dimensions climbs beyond four, it's time to bid this genre adieu, and look for a style that can scale a little better. At any rate, before we proceed any further, let's first assemble the information that we have gathered about <math>F\!</math> from several different angles, and see if it can be fitted into a coherent picture of the transformation <math>F : (u, v) \mapsto ( ~\texttt{((u)(v))}~, ~\texttt{((u, v))}~ ).</math> | + | In my work on [[Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems 2.0|Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems]], I found it useful to develop several different ways of visualizing logical transformations, indeed, I devised four distinct styles of picture for the job. Thus far in our work on the mapping <math>F : [u, v] \to [u, v],\!</math> we've been making use of what I call the ''areal view'' of the extended universe of discourse, <math>[u, v, \mathrm{d}u, \mathrm{d}v],\!</math> but as the number of dimensions climbs beyond four, it's time to bid this genre adieu and look for a style that can scale a little better. At any rate, before we proceed any further, let's first assemble the information that we have gathered about <math>F\!</math> from several different angles, and see if it can be fitted into a coherent picture of the transformation <math>F : (u, v) \mapsto ( ~ \texttt{((} u \texttt{)(} v \texttt{))} ~,~ \texttt{((} u \texttt{,~} v \texttt{))} ~ ).\!</math> |
| | | |
| In our first crack at the transformation <math>F,\!</math> we simply plotted the state transitions and applied the utterly stock technique of calculating the finite differences. | | In our first crack at the transformation <math>F,\!</math> we simply plotted the state transitions and applied the utterly stock technique of calculating the finite differences. |
Line 1,929: |
Line 1,929: |
| | | | | |
| <math>\begin{array}{c|cc|cc|} | | <math>\begin{array}{c|cc|cc|} |
− | t & u & v & du & dv \\[8pt] | + | t & u & v & \mathrm{d}u & \mathrm{d}v \\[8pt] |
− | 0 & 1 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ | + | 0 & 1 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ |
− | 1 & '' & '' & '' & '' \\ | + | 1 & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel |
| \end{array}</math> | | \end{array}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | A quick inspection of the first Table suggests a rule to cover the case when <math>\texttt{u~=~v~=~1},</math> namely, <math>\texttt{du~=~dv~=~0}.</math> To put it another way, the Table characterizes Orbit 1 by means of the data: <math>(u, v, du, dv) = (1, 1, 0, 0).\!</math> Another way to convey the same information is by means of the extended proposition: <math>\texttt{u~v~(du)(dv)}.</math> | + | A quick inspection of the first Table suggests a rule to cover the case when <math>u = v = 1,\!</math> namely, <math>\mathrm{d}u = \mathrm{d}v = 0.\!</math> To put it another way, the Table characterizes Orbit 1 by means of the data: <math>(u, v, \mathrm{d}u, \mathrm{d}v) = (1, 1, 0, 0).\!</math> Another way to convey the same information is by means of the extended proposition: <math>u v \texttt{(} \mathrm{d}u \texttt{)(} \mathrm{d}v \texttt{)}.\!</math> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center" |
Line 1,942: |
Line 1,942: |
| | | | | |
| <math>\begin{array}{c|cc|cc|cc|} | | <math>\begin{array}{c|cc|cc|cc|} |
− | t & u & v & du & dv & d^2 u & d^2 v \\[8pt] | + | t & u & v & \mathrm{d}u & \mathrm{d}v & \mathrm{d}^2 u & \mathrm{d}^2 v \\[8pt] |
− | 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 1 & 0 \\ | + | 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 & 1 & 0 \\ |
− | 1 & 0 & 1 & 1 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\ | + | 1 & 0 & 1 & 1 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\ |
− | 2 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 \\ | + | 2 & 1 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 & 0 \\ |
− | 3 & '' & '' & '' & '' & '' & '' \\ | + | 3 & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel & {}^\shortparallel |
| \end{array}</math> | | \end{array}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | A more fine combing of the second Table brings to mind a rule that partly covers the remaining cases, that is, <math>\texttt{du~=~v}, ~\texttt{dv~=~(u)}.</math> This much information about Orbit 2 is also encapsulated by the extended proposition, <math>\texttt{(uv)((du, v))(dv, u)},</math> which says that <math>u\!</math> and <math>v\!</math> are not both true at the same time, while <math>du\!</math> is equal in value to <math>v\!</math> and <math>dv\!</math> is opposite in value to <math>u.\!</math> | + | A more fine combing of the second Table brings to mind a rule that partly covers the remaining cases, that is, <math>\mathrm{d}u = v, ~ \mathrm{d}v = \texttt{(} u \texttt{)}.\!</math> This much information about Orbit 2 is also encapsulated by the extended proposition <math>\texttt{(} uv \texttt{)((} \mathrm{d}u \texttt{,} v \texttt{))(} \mathrm{d}v, u \texttt{)},\!</math> which says that <math>u\!</math> and <math>v\!</math> are not both true at the same time, while <math>\mathrm{d}u\!</math> is equal in value to <math>v\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{d}v\!</math> is opposite in value to <math>u.\!</math> |
| | | |
| ==Turing Machine Example== | | ==Turing Machine Example== |