Changes

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Tuesday November 26, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
10,370 bytes added ,  15:28, 24 January 2008
copy old work notes to talk page
Line 1: Line 1:  
==Notes & Queries==
 
==Notes & Queries==
[[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 11:44, 17 May 2007 (PDT)
+
 
 +
# [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 15:34, 8 January 2006 (UTC)
 +
# [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 11:44, 17 May 2007 (PDT)
 +
# [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 07:28, 24 January 2008 (PST)
 +
 
 +
===Pragmatic theory of inquiry===
 +
 
 +
===Classical models===
 +
 
 +
JA: I am dumping some raw source material here until I can sort it out.  [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]] 19:26, 14 April 2006 (UTC)
 +
 
 +
References:
 +
 
 +
* [[Aristotle]], "The Categories", [[Harold P. Cooke]] (trans.), pp. 1–109 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'',  [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938.
 +
 
 +
* [[Aristotle]], "On Interpretation", [[Harold P. Cooke]] (trans.), pp. 111–179 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'',  [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938.
 +
 
 +
* [[Aristotle]], "[[Prior Analytics]]", [[Hugh Tredennick]] (trans.), pp. 181–531 in ''Aristotle, Volume 1'', [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1938.
 +
 
 +
* [[Aristotle]], "[[On the Soul]]" (''De Anima''), [[W.S. Hett]] (trans.), pp. 1–203 in ''Aristotle, Volume 8'',  [[Loeb Classical Library]], [[William Heinemann]], London, UK, 1936.
 +
 
 +
<pre>
 +
Appendix A:  Sources
 +
Aristotle:  On Interpretation
 +
Chapter 1
 +
 +
{1} Words spoken are symbols or signs of affections or impressions
 +
of the soul;  written words are the signs of words spoken.  As
 +
writing, so also is speech not the same for all races of men.
 +
But the mental affections themselves, of which these words
 +
are primarily signs, are the same for the whole of mankind,
 +
as are also the objects of which those affections are
 +
representations or likenesses, images, copies.
 +
 +
Aristotle:  Prior Analytics
 +
Book 1 Chapter 4
 +
{1} When three terms are so related to one another that the last
 +
is wholly contained in the middle and the middle is wholly
 +
contained in or excluded from the first, the extremes must admit
 +
of perfect syllogism.  By 'middle term' I mean that which both is
 +
contained in another and contains another in itself, and which is
 +
the middle by its position also; and by 'extremes' (a) that which
 +
is contained in another, and (b) that in which another is
 +
contained.  For if A is predicated of all B, and B of all C,
 +
A must necessarily be predicated of all C.  ...  I call this kind
 +
of figure the First.
 +
 +
Chapter 5
 +
 +
{2} When the same term applies to all of one subject and to none
 +
of the other, or to all or none of both, I call this kind of
 +
figure the Second; and in it by the middle term I mean that which
 +
is predicated of both subjects; by the extreme terms, the subjects
 +
of which the middle is predicated; by the major term, that which
 +
comes next to the middle; and by the minor that which is more
 +
distant from it.  The middle is placed outside the extreme terms,
 +
and is first by position.
 +
 +
Chapter 6
 +
 +
{3} If one of the terms applies to all and the other to none of
 +
the same subject, or if both terms apply to all or none of it,
 +
I call this kind of figure the Third; and in it by the middle I
 +
mean that of which both the predications are made; by extremes
 +
the predicates; by the major term that which is [further from?]
 +
the middle; and by the minor that which is nearer to it.  The
 +
middle is placed outside the extremes, and is last by position.
 +
 +
Book 2 Chapter 21
 +
 +
{1} Similarly too with the theory in the Meno that learning is
 +
recollection.  For in no case do we find that we have previous
 +
knowledge of the individual, but we do find that in the process
 +
of induction we acquire knowledge of particular things just as
 +
though we could remember them; for there are some things which we
 +
know immediately:  e.g., if we know that X is a triangle we know
 +
that the sum of its angles is equal to two right angles.
 +
Similarly too in all other cases.
 +
 +
{2} Thus whereas we observe particular things by universal
 +
knowledge, we do not know them by the knowledge peculiar to them.
 +
Hence it is possible to be mistaken about them, not because we
 +
have contrary knowledge about them, but because, although we have
 +
universal knowledge of them, we are mistaken in our particular
 +
knowledge.
 +
 +
Book 2 Chapter 23
 +
 +
{1} Induction epagwgh, or inductive reasoning, consists in
 +
establishing a relation between one extreme term and the middle
 +
term by means of the other extreme; e.g., if B is the middle term
 +
of A and C, in proving by means of C that A applies to B; for this
 +
is how we effect inductions.  E.g., let A stand for 'long-lived',
 +
B for 'that which has no bile' and C for the long-lived
 +
individuals such as man and horse and mule.  Then A applies to the
 +
whole of C, for every bileless animal is long-lived.  But B, 'not
 +
having bile', also applies to all C.  Then if C is convertible
 +
with B, i.e., if the middle term is not wider in extension,
 +
A must apply to B.
 +
 +
{2} This kind of syllogism is concerned with the first or
 +
immediate premiss.  Where there is a middle term, the syllogism
 +
proceeds by means of the middle; where there is not, it proceeds
 +
by induction.  There is a sense in which induction is opposed to
 +
syllogism, for the latter shows by the middle term that the major
 +
extreme applies to the third, while the former shows by means of
 +
the third that the major extreme applies to the middle.  Thus by
 +
nature the syllogism by means of the middle is prior and more
 +
knowable; but syllogism by induction is more apparent to us.
 +
 +
Book 2 Chapter 24
 +
 +
{1} We have an Example paradeigma when the major extreme is shown
 +
to be applicable to the middle term by means of a term similar to
 +
the third.  It must be known both that the middle applies to the
 +
third term and that the first applies to the term similar to the
 +
third.  E.g., let A be 'bad', B 'to make war on neighbors',
 +
C 'Athens against Thebes' and D 'Thebes against Phocis'.  Then
 +
if we require to prove that war against Thebes is bad, we must be
 +
satisfied that war against neighbors is bad.  Evidence of this can
 +
be drawn from similar examples, e.g., that war by Thebes against
 +
Phocis is bad.  Then since war against neighbors is bad, and war
 +
against Thebes is against neighbors, it is evident that war
 +
against Thebes is bad.  Now it is evident that B applies to C
 +
and D (for they are both examples of making war on neighbors),
 +
and A to D (since the war against Phocis did Thebes no good); but
 +
that A applies to B will be proved by means of D. ...
 +
 +
{2} Thus it is evident that an example represents the relation,
 +
not of part to whole or of whole to part, but of one part to
 +
another, where both are subordinate to the same general term,
 +
and one of them is known.  It differs from induction in that the
 +
latter, as we saw, shows from an examination of all the individual
 +
cases that the [major] extreme applies to the middle, and does not
 +
connect the conclusion with the [minor] extreme; whereas the
 +
example does connect it and does not use all the individual cases
 +
for its proof.
 +
 +
Book 2 Chapter 25
 +
 +
{1} We have Reduction apagwgh (a) when it is obvious that the
 +
first term applies to the middle, but that the middle applies to
 +
the last term is not obvious, yet nevertheless is more probable or
 +
not less probable than the conclusion; or (b) if there are not
 +
many intermediate terms between the last and the middle; for in
 +
all such cases the effect is to bring us nearer to knowledge.
 +
 +
{2} (a) E.g., let A stand for 'that which can be taught', B for
 +
'knowledge' and C for 'morality'.  Then that knowledge can be
 +
taught is evident; but whether virtue is knowledge is not clear.
 +
Then if BC is not less probable or is more probable than AC, we
 +
have reduction; for we are nearer to knowledge for having
 +
introduced an additional term, whereas before we had no knowledge
 +
that AC is true.
 +
 +
{3} (b) Or again we have reduction if there are not many
 +
intermediate terms between B and C; for in this case too we are
 +
brought nearer to knowledge.  E.g., suppose that D is 'to square',
 +
E 'rectilinear figure' and F 'circle'.  Assuming that between
 +
E and F there is only one intermediate term - that the circle
 +
becomes equal to a rectilinear figure by means of lunules -
 +
we should approximate to knowledge.
 +
 +
{4} When, however, BC is not more probable than AC, or there are
 +
several intermediate terms, I do not use the expression
 +
'reduction'; nor when the proposition BC is immediate; for such
 +
a statement implies knowledge.
 +
 +
Book 2 Chapter 27
 +
 +
{1} A probability eikoV is not the same as a sign shmeion.  The
 +
former is a generally accepted premiss; for that which people know
 +
to happen or not to happen, or to be or not to be, usually in a
 +
particular way, is a probability:  e.g., that the envious are
 +
malevolent or that those who are loved are affectionate.  A sign,
 +
however, means a demonstrative premiss which is necessary or
 +
generally accepted.  That which coexists with something else,
 +
or before or after whose happening something else has happened,
 +
is a sign of that something's having happened or being.
 +
 +
{2} An enthymeme is a syllogism from probabilities or signs; and
 +
a sign can be taken in three ways - in just as many ways as there
 +
are of taking the middle term in the several figures ...
 +
 +
{3} We must either classify signs in this way, and regard their
 +
middle term as an index tekmhrion (for the name 'index' is given
 +
to that which causes us to know, and the middle term is especially
 +
of this nature), or describe the arguments drawn from the extremes
 +
as 'signs', and that which is drawn from the middle as an 'index'.
 +
For the conclusion which is reached through the first figure is
 +
most generally accepted and most true.
 +
 +
Aristotle:  The Art of Rhetoric
 +
 +
Book 1 Chapter 2
 +
 +
{1} But for purposes of demonstration, real or apparent, just as
 +
Dialectic possesses two modes of argument, induction and the
 +
syllogism, real or apparent, the same is the case in Rhetoric;
 +
for the example is induction, and the enthymeme a syllogism, and
 +
the apparent enthymeme an apparent syllogism.  Accordingly I call
 +
an enthymeme a rhetorical syllogism, and an example rhetorical
 +
induction.
 +
 +
{2} But since few of the propositions of the rhetorical syllogism
 +
are necessary, ... it is evident that the materials from which
 +
enthymemes are derived will be sometimes necessary, but for the
 +
most part only generally true; and these materials being
 +
probabilities and signs, it follows that these two elements must
 +
correspond to these two kinds of propositions, each to each.  ...
 +
</pre>
12,080

edits

Navigation menu