Changes

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Sunday November 24, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
Line 2,252: Line 2,252:  
By way of concrete examples, FOJs of a negative character frequently arise in situations that are affected by a genuine dilemma, where it is necessary to choose just one action from a set of two or more actions, where it is impossible to do nothing and impossible to do everything, and where each action excludes all the others.  At such a juncture the structure of that very situation, or a reference to it as described, is itself a sufficiently valid FOJ for choosing some action, even if not yet a full justification for any one specific choice.  If an agent challenged:  “Why did you do that?”, responds:  “It was necessary to do something!”, then that is “just” as far as it goes, to a general not a specific extent.  In summary, one finds that there are FOJs of a negative character, that proceed by the rejection of an alternative, but that are perfectly valid in their doing so.  These FOJs of a negative character exist in contrast to the more familiar FOJs, at least, the more often expressed FOJs, all of which are positive and transitive in character, identical or analogous to the various forms of logical implication and logical consequence.
 
By way of concrete examples, FOJs of a negative character frequently arise in situations that are affected by a genuine dilemma, where it is necessary to choose just one action from a set of two or more actions, where it is impossible to do nothing and impossible to do everything, and where each action excludes all the others.  At such a juncture the structure of that very situation, or a reference to it as described, is itself a sufficiently valid FOJ for choosing some action, even if not yet a full justification for any one specific choice.  If an agent challenged:  “Why did you do that?”, responds:  “It was necessary to do something!”, then that is “just” as far as it goes, to a general not a specific extent.  In summary, one finds that there are FOJs of a negative character, that proceed by the rejection of an alternative, but that are perfectly valid in their doing so.  These FOJs of a negative character exist in contrast to the more familiar FOJs, at least, the more often expressed FOJs, all of which are positive and transitive in character, identical or analogous to the various forms of logical implication and logical consequence.
   −
<pre>
+
The dictum to the effect that ''there is no argument in matters of taste'', for what it is worth, enjoins an ''argument to'', not an ''argument from''.  An aesthetic principle or judgment, that I prefer to live, for example, can have definite logical consequences, even if every justification I can expect to find for it is ultimately circular, tautologous, or logically speaking, trivial in form:  &ldquo;Why do I like it?&rdquo; &mdash; &ldquo;Just because I do!&rdquo;  To me, this cannot help but seem, if challenged in a case of this kind, to be a perfectly adequate and a reasonably sufficient answer.  But to maintain this reason means to preserve this life, and that in its turn has decidedly logical consequences.  It is likely that artisans and engineers have an easier time understanding this pragmatic principle, what it means in active practice and the wisdom it holds in general, than many varieties of logicians, mathematicians, philosophers, and scientists, although if I say that I pick my axioms with an eye to the beauty of what they can shape, in other words, that I select my logical and mathematical principles for what are essentially aesthetic reasons, then there are evidently some in these guilded ilks who already know what I mean.
The dictum to the effect that "there is no argument in matters of taste", for what it is worth, enjoins an "argument to", not an "argument from".  An aesthetic principle or judgment, that I prefer to live, for example, can have definite logical consequences, even if every justification I can expect to find for it is ultimately circular, tautologous, or logically speaking, trivial in form:  "Why do I like it?" — "Just because I do!" To me, this cannot help but seem, if challenged in a case of this kind, to be a perfectly adequate and a reasonably sufficient answer.  But to maintain this reason means to preserve this life, and that in its turn has decidedly logical consequences.  It is likely that artisans and engineers have an easier time understanding this pragmatic principle, what it means in active practice and the wisdom it holds in general, than many varieties of logicians, mathematicians, philosophers, and scientists, although if I say that I pick my axioms with an eye to the beauty of what they can shape, in other words, that I select my logical and mathematical principles for what are essentially aesthetic reasons, then there are evidently some in these guilded ilks who already know what I mean.
     −
Socrates not only used irony but was so dedicated to irony that he himself succumbed to it.
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" width="90%"
Kierkegaard, The Concept of Irony, [Kier, 5]
+
|
 +
<p>Socrates not only used irony but was so dedicated to irony that he himself succumbed to it.</p>
 +
|-
 +
| align="right" | Kierkegaard, ''The Concept of Irony'', [Kier, 5]
 +
|}
    
A person who drinks an extract of hemlock for what he says is a reason of logic either suffers from a confusion of priorities or acts according to a higher aesthetic than that of saving his own small portion of life.  But a person who drains the tendered glass for lack of lighting quickly enough on a reason why not is a person who has let his extract of logic turn to a poison in its own right.
 
A person who drinks an extract of hemlock for what he says is a reason of logic either suffers from a confusion of priorities or acts according to a higher aesthetic than that of saving his own small portion of life.  But a person who drains the tendered glass for lack of lighting quickly enough on a reason why not is a person who has let his extract of logic turn to a poison in its own right.
</pre>
      
=====5.2.11.7. The Experience of Satisfaction=====
 
=====5.2.11.7. The Experience of Satisfaction=====
12,080

edits

Navigation menu