Difference between revisions of "User:Jon Awbrey/TEST"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Friday November 22, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
(→‎Test Area: Text 2)
 
(4 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
==Test Area==
 
==Test Area==
  
<pre>
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="0" cellspacing="0" width="90%"
Interpretation as Action: The Risk of Inquiry
+
|
 +
<p>A child hears it said that the stove is hot.  But it is not, he says;  and, indeed, that central body is not touching it, and only what that touches is hot or cold.  But he touches it, and finds the testimony confirmed in a striking way.  Thus, he becomes aware of ignorance, and it is necessary to suppose a ''self'' in which this ignorance can inhere.  &hellip;</p>
  
Jon Awbrey and Susan Awbrey
+
<p>In short, ''error'' appears, and it can be explained only by supposing a ''self'' which is fallible.</p>
  
"We hope you will find these thoughts of ours both interesting and useful." These are words spoken to express an intention, a bearing in
+
<p>Ignorance and error are all that distinguish our private selves from the absolute ''ego'' of pure apperception.</p>
 
+
|-
the mind of a person toward an object which is yet to be achieved. The readiest moment of human life involves the interplay of signs,
+
| align="right" | (Peirce, CP 5.233&ndash;235)
 
+
|}
ideas, and objects-more explicitly, the interrelation of signifying expressions, states and dispositions of the mind or person, and
 
 
 
objects or objectives either actual or potential. Our work designing instruments to enhance the play of inquiry has attuned us to the
 
 
 
themes of interpretation and intentionality which every inquiry seems to involve. We hear what sounds like familiar strains reaching us
 
 
 
from the hermeneutic quarter. The purpose of this essay is to trace to their sources a few of these potentially common themes, to draw out
 
 
 
one line of their historical development, and to gather what consequences they inspire for educational practice and continued inquiry.
 
 
 
Introduction
 
 
 
In order to study the nature of signification and communication, the theory of signs must involve itself with questions of interpretation
 
 
 
and intention. The theory of inquiry studies the common pattern of all determination, all proceeding toward the settlement of unsettled
 
 
 
situations. There is a key relationship between signs and inquiry. We will follow this relationship through three points of reference.
 
 
 
Aristotle's Peri Hermeneias or On Interpretation introduces the relationship of signs, impressions in the mind, and objects. C.S. Peirce
 
 
 
fully explores the triadic relation of signs, interpretants, and objects in its bearing upon his threestage process of inquiry. John Dewey
 
 
 
elaborates these ideas in his view of the lived experience as the "existential matrix" of inquiry. Three major questions will be explored:
 
 
 
How does the sign relation that underlies the nature of signification and communication compare within these works?
 
 
 
We discuss the role of the interpreter in the activity of interpretation. Aristotle assumes that objects and impressions in the mind are
 
 
 
constant across all interpreters. Confronting this assumption with the needs of hermeneutic and educational practice, we argue that a
 
 
 
comparative and developmental understanding of interpreters is required. This in turn demands the more complete theory of signs envisioned
 
 
 
by Peirce and Dewey, which continues to be developed in the semiotic and pragmatic traditions.
 
 
 
What is inquiry and how is it related to the theory of signs?
 
 
 
We examine the structure of inquiry as articulated by Peirce and Dewey. In this model, inquiry begins with a surprising phenomenon or
 
 
 
problematic situation. Whether felt as pleasant wonderment or painful bewilderment, we feel driven to some activity that will return us to
 
 
 
our prior equilibrium. This may issue in a search for explanation that reduces the surprise or for a plan of action that resolves the
 
 
 
problem. The ensuing activities share a common form, the differentiation of a pattern. In our consternation, we recognize a variety of
 
 
 
features, some of which can be varied as part of our capacity for free choice. The problem or surprise is present because of its
 
 
 
difference from something. As a surprise, what happens is different from what we habitually expect. As a problem, what happens is
 
 
 
different from what we hopefully intend. To change the systematic expectation against which background a surprising phenomenon originally
 
 
 
figured, we must discover some freedom to change what generated that expectation, and so to modify our personal model of the world.
 
 
 
What do these ideas suggest for the practice of education?
 
 
 
A variety of implications will be explored. In this view, the teacher acts as a catalyst of inquiry, serving as a mediator to quicken the
 
 
 
actualization of something already present in the potential of the student. Emphasis is placed on developing tools that extend the
 
 
 
learner's capacity for inquiry. The authors' goal is to design computer software that will enhance the capacity for exploring complex,
 
 
 
qualitative information and will support inquiry by serving as a bridge between teaching and research. By engaging in their own
 
 
 
explorations and making assumptions explicit, learners will be invited to "think reflectively" about their interpretations.
 
 
 
The Theory of Signs and the Role of the Interpreter
 
 
 
We accept the tenet of pragmatism that all thought takes place in signs. Our interest in the enterprise of "training thought" (Dewey 1991)
 
 
 
demands that we examine the role of the interpreter in all the activities that make use of or take place in signs.
 
 
 
Aristotle On Interpretation
 
 
 
Our first point of reference is Aristotle's introduction of the sign relation in his treatise On Interpretation.
 
 
 
Words spoken are symbols or signs (symbola) of affections or impressions (pathemata) of the soul (psyche); written words are the signs of
 
 
 
words spoken. As writing, so also is speech not the same for all races of men. But the mental affections themselves, of which these words
 
 
 
are primarily signs (semeia), are the same for the whole of mankind, as are also the objects (pragmata) of which those affections are
 
 
 
representations or likenesses, images, copies (homoiomata). (Aristotle, De Interp. i. 16a4).
 
 
 
This early text recognizes the three roles within the sign relation: signs, ideas, and objects. It also characterizes the relationships
 
 
 
between these three roles. For Aristotle, the relation between signs (words) and ideas (affections and impressions) is that of a symbol to
 
 
 
what it symbolizes. In origin, a symbol was a split coin used as a token of recognition. In concrete terms, the symbol is a particular
 
 
 
kind of sign. As a fragment, it refers both to its other half and to the whole that they originally formed. The relation between ideas and
 
 
 
objects is that of an impression to what it is a likeness of. Although Aristotle leaves it implicit, we can see that there is a
 
 
 
relationship between signs and objects that is a compound of the first two relations. It is the indirect relation, a fragment of a
 
 
 
likeness. There is irony here, that the sign relation is rooted in a type of iconoclasm.
 
 
 
Figure 1 illustrates the sign relation as described by Aristotle. The arrows are drawn to indicate the direction of increasing
 
 
 
symbolization, proceeding around the faces of the sign relation in an opposite sense from the process of adducing meaning which it is the
 
 
 
job of interpretation to reconstruct. The interpreter, as agent and embodiment of all the various sign processes, does not have a
 
 
 
particular role in the sign relation but is, in a sense, identified with the whole of it.
 
 
 
Figure 1. The Sign Relation in Aristotle
 
 
 
Aristotle's description contains two claims of constancy, that ideas and objects are the same for all interpreters. This view does not
 
 
 
allow for the plurality and mutability of interpreters, two features that we must be concerned with in hermeneutics and education. John
 
 
 
Dewey expresses this point well:
 
 
 
Thinking is specific, in that different things suggest their own appropriate meanings, tell their own unique stories, and in that they do
 
 
 
this in very different ways with different persons. (Dewey 1991, 39).
 
 
 
However, this account of Aristotle's may be considered in part a reasonable approximation and in part a suggestive metaphor, suitable as a
 
 
 
first approach to a complex subject.
 
 
 
Some other features of this text will figure in our later discussions. Pragmata, the Greek word used for "objects," has shades of meaning
 
 
 
ranging from physical objects to purposeful objectives to problematic objections. Derivatives of it can refer to troubles and treatises,
 
 
 
all very much the business of inquiry. These objects became the "going concerns" of pragmatism. However, the attempt of pragmatists to
 
 
 
convey these varied meanings in practice was often misconstrued as a reduction of intentions to physical operations. One last point of
 
 
 
interest, the text suggests that Aristotle appreciated the tension between cultural and natural signs by employing words with both
 
 
 
connotations (symbola vs. semeia).
 
 
 
The Sign Relation According to Peirce
 
 
 
In moving from Aristotle's account of the sign relation to Peirce's, it helps to identify some links between them. Words spoken or written
 
 
 
are classed together as Signs. Ideas, affections and impressions, correspond to what Peirce calls Interpretants. For all practical
 
 
 
purposes, interpretants are just another class of signs. They may even be just another role the same class of signs can play. If any
 
 
 
distinction is intended between them, it is only that interpretants are more intimately involved in the mind or person of the Interpreter.
 
 
 
Peirce gave the following definition of a sign in his 1902 Application to the Carnegie Institution:
 
 
 
Logic is formal semiotic. A sign is something, A, which brings something, B, its interpretant sign, determined or created by it, into the
 
 
 
same sort of correspondence (or a lower implied sort) with something, C, its object, as that in which itself stands to C. This definition
 
 
 
no more involves any reference to human thought than does the definition of a line as the place within which a particle lies during a
 
 
 
lapse of time. (Peirce, NE 4, 54).
 
 
 
There are two important features to note in this portrayal of the role of signs in logic. First, Peirce's goal is to differentiate the
 
 
 
formal and the material aspects of thought and inquiry. This attempt is motivated by his interest in a certain question: "What is the
 
 
 
relation of matter and form in the actuality of the mind (entelechy) and is their synthesis a third something or not? This helps us
 
 
 
understand how Peirce can be concerned with developing a formal characterization of signs and sign processes without being just another
 
 
 
"formalist." His interest is partly due to the influence of Aristotle, whose dictum that "soul is form" is given in the following text:
 
 
 
So the soul (psyche) must be substance (ousia) in the sense of being the form (eidos) of a natural body (soma), which potentially
 
 
 
(dynamei) has life. And substance in this sense is actuality (entelecheia). (Aristotle, De Anima II.i. 412a20).
 
 
 
Second, Peirce's claim that his definition of a sign involves no reference to human thought means no necessary reference. The adjective
 
 
 
"nonpsychological" that he often attaches to this conception of signs and logic is not intended to be exclusive of human thought but to
 
 
 
expand the scope of the concepts beyond it (Peirce, NE 4, 21). The prefix "non" is better read as an acronym for "not of necessity," and
 
 
 
is commonly used in mathematical discourse in just this way. It extends the use of a concept into wider domains than the paradigm cases
 
 
 
upon which our original intuitions were formed.
 
 
 
A definition of signs and their processes which is not limited by prior restriction to human psychology can be used to investigate human
 
 
 
thought as a species of natural process. There is considerable power in this naturalistic viewpoint. It allows us to put human thought in
 
 
 
a context of other sign processes, to ask what might be the specific differences that distinguish it, and to consider its evolution
 
 
 
through different orders of complexity.
 
 
 
Two other features of the sign relation, as portrayed by Peirce, are especially crucial. First, the designations sign, interpretant, and
 
 
 
object are pragmatic roles and not attributes of real essence or permanent nature. Second, a sign relation in the generic case can be
 
 
 
irreducibly triadic, and as such cannot be wholly understood from any compound of its dyadic fractions.
 
 
 
Pragmatic Roles vs. Exclusive Attributes
 
 
 
The assignments of entities to the roles of sign, interpretant, and object do not mark any distinctions of essence or substantial
 
 
 
differences among these entities. The same entity may function in any role. For example, Queen Elizabeth may be a symbol of her realm to
 
 
 
her subjects; but as a person, she is an interpreter of the English language. Of course, some things may be found more suitable than
 
 
 
others for a given role, but this is a pragmatic factor and discovered after the fact. These attributions are exactly that, roles
 
 
 
attributed to an entity from a certain point of view, and correctly attributed only in relation to its moment by moment functioning in a
 
 
 
currently relevant sign process.
 
 
 
Sign Relations are Irreducibly Triadic
 
 
 
What does it mean that a sign relation is irreducibly triadic? In simplest terms it means that there are facts about a sign relation which
 
 
 
cannot be pieced together from separate investigations of the pairwise relations. Thus, studies which limit themselves to syntax
 
 
 
(relations internal to the sign domain) or semantics (relations between signs and objects) or semiotics (relations between signs and
 
 
 
interpretants), all necessary to the topic, are not sufficient to capture the full dimensionality of the subject. Pragmatics is the name
 
 
 
we use for the full theory of signs, one that provides for the consideration of plurality and progress in the analysis of interpreters.
 
 
 
Why is it important that a sign relation is irreducibly triadic? In our general effort to understand complex phenomena using the simpler
 
 
 
things we already understand as guides, the irreducibly triadic nature of signs brings both good news and bad news. The bad news we have
 
 
 
already seen. There is no hope of fully understanding the sign relation in terms of anything simpler. The good news is this. If we do
 
 
 
become accustomed to things as complex as the sign relation, then many other interesting phenomena can be clarified by using it. Indeed,
 
 
 
it is our impression that at least some of the tensions in the issue of intentionality can be resolved by relating them to similar
 
 
 
tensions in the sign relation.
 
 
 
Signs and Inquiry, Information and Doubt
 
 
 
When we call attention to the fact that signs and expressions are human artifacts, it forces us to recognize that signs are objects in
 
 
 
their own right, with all the contingency and facticity that this entails. It is only natural that in pointing out the status of a sign as
 
 
 
sign, we are reminded of its fallibility, the chance that it can fail to mean anything either present or forthcoming, the risk that it may
 
 
 
lead or mislead by degrees in its aim. The sign may be broken in numerous ways, failing to connect by not denoting or not connoting,
 
 
 
losing its relation to objects in the world or ideas in the mind. All the ways that it can succeed are ways that it can fail to signify.
 
 
 
What is frequently appreciated in many so-called symbols is exactly their vagueness, their openness, their fruitful ineffectiveness in
 
 
 
expressing a "final" meaning, so that with symbols and by symbols one indicates what is always beyond one's reach. (Eco 1986, 153).
 
 
 
The fallibility of signs is shared with the human activities of interpretation and inquiry, and bears a relation to the situated character
 
 
 
of all dynamic processes of determination.
 
 
 
If doubt and indeterminateness were wholly within the mind-whatever that may signify - purely mental processes ought to get rid of them.
 
 
 
But experimental procedure signifies that actual alteration of an external situation is necessary to effect the conversion. A situation
 
 
 
undergoes, through operations directed by thought, transition from problematic to settled, from internal discontinuity to coherency and
 
 
 
organization. (Dewey 1988, 185).
 
 
 
Signs are enabled to have significance only within a proper setting. A whole system of signs is required to constitute what we variously
 
 
 
call a medium, a channel, a formal or natural language. In such a context, information becomes a property that we attribute to signs. A
 
 
 
sign given in this kind of situation has the ability to reduce the uncertainty that an interpreter has with regard to an object domain. It
 
 
 
is in virtue of this ability that a sign is said to possess and convey information.
 
 
 
This power of reducing uncertainty, of mediating between the less and the more determinate situation, is just the virtue that inquiry
 
 
 
seeks to have. Our established systems of signs are the typical results of wellcompleted inquiries, while inquiries in the present tense
 
 
 
have no guarantee of yielding such stable and reusable products.
 
 
 
The Pattern and Stages of Inquiry
 
 
 
Up until now we proceeded synthetically, attempting to reconstruct the nature of inquiry from the shape and flow of its chief
 
 
 
constituents, signs in action. We now move inquiry into the foreground, examining the functions and stages which support it. In doing
 
 
 
this, it is natural to reverse the order of presentation and to work from our current perspective on signs toward the functional and
 
 
 
historical precursors which round out our view of inquiry.
 
 
 
To illustrate the place of the sign relation in inquiry we begin with Dewey's elegant and simple example of reflective thinking in
 
 
 
everyday life:
 
 
 
A man is walking on a warm day. The sky was clear the last time he observed it; but presently he notes, while occupied primarily with
 
 
 
other things, that the air is cooler. It occurs to him that it is probably going to rain; looking up, he sees a dark cloud between him and
 
 
 
the sun, and he then quickens his steps. What, if anything, in such a situation can be called thought? Neither the act of walking nor the
 
 
 
noting of the cold is a thought. Walking is one direction of activity; looking and noting are other modes of activity. The likelihood that
 
 
 
it will rain is, however, something suggested. The pedestrian feels the cold; he thinks of clouds and a coming shower. (Dewey 1991, 6-7).
 
 
 
In this narrative we can identify the characters of the sign relation as follows: coolness is a Sign of the Object rain, and the
 
 
 
Interpretant is the thought of the rain's likelihood. In his 1910 description of reflective thinking Dewey distinguishes two phases, "a
 
 
 
state of perplexity, hesitation, doubt" and "an act of search or investigation" (Dewey 1991, 9), comprehensive stages which are further
 
 
 
refined in his later model of inquiry. In this example, reflection is the act of the interpreter which establishes a fund of connections
 
 
 
between the sensory shock of coolness and the objective danger of rain, by way of his impression that rain is likely. But reflection is
 
 
 
more than irresponsible speculation. In reflection the interpreter acts to charge or defuse the thought of rain (the probability of rain
 
 
 
in thought) by seeking other signs which this thought implies and evaluating the thought according to the results of this search.
 
 
 
Figure 2 illustrates Dewey's "Rain" example, tracing the structure and function of the sign relation as it informs the activity of
 
 
 
inquiry, including both the movements of surprise explanation and intentional action. The dyadic faces of the sign relation are labeled
 
 
 
with just a few of the loosest terms that apply, indicating the "significance" of signs for eventual occurrences and the "correspondence"
 
 
 
of ideas with external orientations. Nothing essential is meant by these dyadic role distinctions, since it is only in special or
 
 
 
degenerate cases that their shadowy projections can maintain enough information to determine the original sign relation.
 
 
 
Figure 2. Signs and Inquiry in Dewey
 
 
 
If we follow this example far enough to consider the import of thought for action, we realize that the subsequent conduct of the
 
 
 
interpreter, progressing up through the natural conclusion of the episode-the quickening steps, seeking shelter in time to escape the
 
 
 
rain-all of these acts form a series of further interpretants, contingent on the active causes of the individual, for the originally
 
 
 
recognized signs of rain and for the first impressions of the actual case. Just as critical reflection develops the associated and
 
 
 
alternative signs which gather about an idea, pragmatic interpretation explores the consequential and contrasting actions which give
 
 
 
effective and testable meaning to a person's belief in it.
 
 
 
Dewey's Definition of Inquiry
 
 
 
By 1938 Dewey had developed a definition of inquiry which summarized his mature views:
 
 
 
Inquiry is the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent
 
 
 
distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole. (Dewey 1986, 108).
 
 
 
In view of the apparently inextricable relationship our previous discussions have detected between interpretation and inquiry, it would
 
 
 
seem natural that a definition of inquiry should have some bearing on interpretation. Given Dewey's definition of inquiry, this forces the
 
 
 
question: Can both interpretation and inquiry be seen as special types of determination?
 
 
 
Prior to our discussion of the sign relation, an affirmative answer to this question might have seemed surprising, because these two
 
 
 
things seem so different. Interpretation and inquiry are not usually identified with each other in everyday thought. Interpretation gives
 
 
 
meanings to signs. Inquiry seeks to end perplexity. Interpretation of everyday speech is not reflected upon as problematic, whereas
 
 
 
inquiry is the very model of problem-solving activity.
 
 
 
But now the idea that interpretation is every bit as risky as inquiry should be familiar. There is no infallible reflex which gives
 
 
 
meanings to signs, expressions, and texts. Conversely, inquiry, "thinking" in its best sense, "is a term denoting the various ways in
 
 
 
which things acquire significance" (Dewey 1991, 38). So, there is no longer an obstacle to viewing these two processes as forms of
 
 
 
determination.
 
 
 
Architecture of Inquiry
 
 
 
Peirce and Dewey gave similar accounts of the architecture of inquiry, its typical pattern and generic stages. Both Peirce and Dewey agree
 
 
 
that inquiry is "a response by human beings to some break or interruption in their previously untroubled behavior." In Dewey's later
 
 
 
thought, the stages of inquiry involve: (1) "the problem implicit in such an interruption is located, formulated, and developed"; (2)
 
 
 
"hypotheses (or suggestions) for solving the problem are introduced and are examined, with a view to determining by reasoning just what is
 
 
 
implied by them"; (3) "a hypothesis is tested by appropriate experiments which either verify or disconfirm such logical consequences of
 
 
 
the hypothesis"; and (4) "a judgment as to whether a proposed hypothesis does (or does not) resolve the problem that initiated the
 
 
 
inquiry." (All quotes in this paragraph are from Nagel, in Dewey 1986, xv-xvi).
 
 
 
Peirce's most elegant and detailed account of inquiry is given in the context of his 1908 article "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of
 
 
 
God" (CP 6.468-476). According to Peirce, inquiry begins with "some surprising phenomenon, some experience which either disappoints an
 
 
 
expectation, or breaks in upon some habit of expectation of the inquisiturus."
 
 
 
The first functional stage of inquiry is abduction, which involves "pondering these phenomena in all their aspects," allowing a conjecture
 
 
 
to arise "that furnishes a possible Explanation," regarding the conjecture with "favor" and holding it to be "Plausible." Abduction is the
 
 
 
"whole series of mental performances between the notice of the wonderful phenomenon and the acceptance of the hypothesis." It is:
 
 
 
the dark laboring, the bursting out of the startling conjecture, the remarking of its smooth fitting to the anomaly, as it is turned back
 
 
 
and forth like a key in a lock, and the final estimation of its Plausibility, … Its characteristic formula of reasoning I term
 
 
 
Retroduction [abduction], i.e. reasoning from consequent to antecedent. (Peirce, CP 6.469).
 
 
 
Peirce's second stage of inquiry, deduction, is the testing of the hypothesis.
 
 
 
This testing, to be logically valid, must honestly start, not as Retroduction starts, with scrutiny of the phenomena, but with examination
 
 
 
of the hypothesis, and a muster of all sorts of conditional experiential consequences which would follow from its truth.
 
(Peirce, CP 6.470).
 
 
 
Finally, in the third stage, induction, the inquirer ascertains "how far those consequents accord with Experience, and of judging
 
 
 
accordingly whether the hypothesis is sensibly correct."
 
(Peirce, CP 6.472).
 
 
 
Peirce divides the stages of inquiry at different points than Dewey, relating them to three modes of inference that he calls abductive,
 
 
 
deductive, and inductive reasoning. (Abduction suffers a flight of fanciful names from hypothesis, through presumption and suggestion, to
 
 
 
retroduction.) These forms of inference were drawn from Aristotle's three figures of syllogism and passed through a series of
 
 
 
metamorphoses in Peirce's refractory. Though they follow one another in the typical progress of inquiry, these elements of inference may
 
 
 
also be combined in other ways, for example, to yield mixed forms of reasoning such as analogy (Peirce 1982, 180).
 
 
 
Implications for Educational Practice
 
 
 
According to John Dewey, it is because of the human quest for perfect certainty that philosophy has inherited three problematic
 
 
 
viewpoints:
 
 
 
the first, that certainty, security, can be found only in the fixed and unchanging;
 
the second, that knowledge is the only road to that which is intrinsically stable and certain; the third, that practical activity is an
 
 
 
inferior sort of thing, necessary simply because of man's animal nature and the necessity for winning subsistence from the environment.
 
 
 
(Dewey, 1988, 41).
 
 
 
These predispositions of philosophy toward antecedent, fixed universals have led to what Peirce and Dewey call a spectator theory of
 
 
 
knowledge which "excludes any element of practical activity that enters into the construction of the object known" (Dewey 1988, xi). Still
 
 
 
it is not the uncertainty itself for which Dewey believes we lack tolerance but the risk that it entails. In contrast with invariants the
 
 
 
results of action, even action painstakingly planned and conceived, can never be certain. Its outcomes are only probable. What then can
 
 
 
inquiry offer that the spectator theory of knowledge cannot? Instead of the pursuit of invariant objects as the foundation of certainty,
 
 
 
inquiry affords a feeling of control based on discovering the "relations among changes in place of definition of objects immutable beyond
 
 
 
the possibility of alteration" (Dewey 1988, 82). No longer are we passive receptacles of facts but actively involved explorers, constantly
 
 
 
interpreting our experiences.
 
 
 
Teacher as Catalyst
 
 
 
In this view the teacher acts as a catalyst of student inquiry, serving as a mediator or sign to quicken the actualization of something
 
 
 
already present in the potential of the student. The student's impulse is the 'moving spring' of inquiry, but impulse does not direct
 
 
 
intelligent inquiry. It is purpose that shapes reflective inquiry - "A purpose differs from an original impulse and desire through its
 
 
 
translation into a plan and method of action based upon foresight of the consequences of acting under given observed conditions in a
 
 
 
certain way" (Dewey 1963, 69). Such purposes are formed through observation, experience (both first hand and as information obtained from
 
 
 
those who have wider experience), and judgment which puts observation and experience together to determine what is "signified" (Dewey
 
 
 
1963, 69). To nurture this process teachers can create environments where blind action (impulse) is not an end in itself but where
 
 
 
experiences build the habits of reflective inquiry. Reflective thinking, "active, persistent, and careful consideration of any belief or
 
 
 
supposed form of knowledge in the light of the grounds that support it, and the further conclusions to which it tends" (Dewey 1991, 6) is
 
 
 
indeed the process of inquiry.
 
 
 
Suspending Conclusions and Questioning Assumptions
 
 
 
The inquiry process demands that we suspend our conclusions and tolerate the lack of mental ease created by uncertainty until alternatives
 
 
 
have been examined. We must overcome the tendency to jump at the first suggestion that presents itself. Habermas has said that it is not
 
 
 
entirely our judgments but also our prejudices that determine our being since they are "the conditions whereby we experience something-
 
 
 
whereby what we encounter says something to us" (Bernstein 1971, 97). Reflective thinking is then also critical thinking, "calling into
 
 
 
question the assumptions underlying our customary, habitual ways of thinking and acting and then being ready to think and act differently
 
 
 
on the basis of this critical questioning" (Brookfield 1991, 1).
 
 
 
This reflective operation as we've seen can be triggered by a surprise or a perplexity that we seek to bring to a more settled state.
 
 
 
Today, there is no shortage of such events. "As people try to make sense of these externally imposed changes, they are frequently at
 
 
 
teachable moments as far as the process of becoming critical thinkers is concerned" (Brookfield 1991, 10). Teachers who desire to develop
 
 
 
the habits of inquiry in their students might do well to consider the characteristics of critical teachers described by Freire which
 
 
 
include competence in communicating the possibility of alternative interpretations, the courage to challenge assumptions, willingness to
 
 
 
risk being fully engaged in the educational exchange, humility, and the political clarity to recognize distorting perspectives (Brookfield
 
 
 
1991, 82). However, it must also be noted that teachers, as human beings, have values and prejudices of their own. Recognition of these
 
 
 
assumptions and beliefs to ourselves and to our students is an important part of teaching reflective thinking. It involves the willingness
 
 
 
to examine our biases in the light of student perspectives.
 
 
 
Building Tools for Inquiry
 
 
 
However, such attitudes are not enough. Emphasis is further placed on developing tools that extend the learner's capacity for inquiry and
 
 
 
reflective thinking. "The important thing in the history of modern knowing is the reinforcement of these active doings by means of
 
 
 
instruments … devised for the purposes of disclosing relations not otherwise apparent" (Dewey 1988, 70). Thinking reflectively about our
 
 
 
own practice, the education of children and adults and the development and use of computer technology, has led the authors to a belief in
 
 
 
the value of guided inquiry as educational method and to the use of the computer as a tool for active learning.
 
 
 
Because of its capacities for interaction, modeling and feedback, the computer has the potential to open new educational horizons. The
 
 
 
authors' goal is to develop computer software that will enhance the ability of learners to experience and explore their own worlds-to form
 
 
 
more settled interpretations of the relationships observed, and to examine and reinterpret the assumptions forming their world models.
 
 
 
Because the complexity of qualitative information often makes the process of observation overwhelming, such new tools are needed to
 
 
 
explore the depths of qualitative information, to recognize its patterns, and to interpret its significance. The second goal of this
 
 
 
software is to reduce the gap between teaching and research by empowering learners to work more directly on information gathered for
 
 
 
research. Finally, the third goal is to model the flow of each learner's inquiry and to highlight the individual student's implicit
 
 
 
assumptions. By engaging in personal explorations and making assumptions explicit, individual learners will be invited to "think
 
 
 
reflectively" about their distinctive and shared interpretations.
 
 
 
References
 
 
 
Aristotle, (1983). Prior analytics. In G.P Goold (Ed.) & H. Tredennick (Trans.), Aristotle (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
 
 
 
Press.
 
 
 
_____. (1986). On the soul. In G.P Goold (Ed.) & W.S. Hett (Trans.), Aristotle (Vol. 8). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
 
 
 
Bernstein, R.J. (1971). Praxis and action: Contemporary philosophies of human activity. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania
 
 
 
Press.
 
 
 
_____. (1986). Philosophical profiles. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
 
 
 
Brookfield, S.D. (1991). Developing critical thinkers: Challenging adults to explore alternative ways of thinking and acting. San
 
 
 
Francisco, CA: JosseyBass Publishers.
 
 
 
Dewey, J. (1963). Experience and education. New York, NY: Macmillan Publishing Company. Originally published 1938.
 
 
 
_____. (1986). Logic: The theory of inquiry. In J.A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works, 1925-1953. (Vol 12: 1938). Carbondale,
 
 
 
IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
 
 
 
_____. (1988). The quest for certainty. In J.A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works, 1925-1953. (Vol 4: 1929). Carbondale, IL:
 
 
 
Southern Illinois University Press.
 
 
 
_____. (1991). How we think. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Originally published 1910.
 
 
 
Eco, U. (1986). On symbols. In J. Deely, B. Williams, & F.E. Kruse (Eds.), Frontiers in semiotics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University
 
 
 
Press.
 
 
 
Peirce, C.S. (1960). A neglected argument for the reality of God. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), Collected papers of Charles Sanders
 
 
 
Peirce, (Vol. 6: Scientific metaphysics). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Originally published 1908.
 
 
 
_____. (1976). Parts of Carnegie application. In C. Eisele (Ed.), The new elements of mathematics (Vol. 4). The Hague, Mouton Publishers.
 
 
 
Original letter dated 1902.
 
 
 
_____. (1982). On the logic of science. In Peirce Edition Project (Eds.), Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A chronological edition. (Vol. 1:
 
 
 
1857-1866). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Original lecture dated 1865.
 
 
 
An earlier version of this paper was presented at The Eleventh International Human Science Research Conference, June 1992, Rochester,
 
 
 
Michigan.</pre>
 

Latest revision as of 13:28, 22 February 2012

Test Area

A child hears it said that the stove is hot. But it is not, he says; and, indeed, that central body is not touching it, and only what that touches is hot or cold. But he touches it, and finds the testimony confirmed in a striking way. Thus, he becomes aware of ignorance, and it is necessary to suppose a self in which this ignorance can inhere. …

In short, error appears, and it can be explained only by supposing a self which is fallible.

Ignorance and error are all that distinguish our private selves from the absolute ego of pure apperception.

(Peirce, CP 5.233–235)