\(\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{G}
& = & \operatorname{e}:\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{f}:\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{g}:\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{h}:\operatorname{h}
\'"`UNIQ-MathJax2-QINU`"' is the relate, \(j\!\) is the correlate, and in our current example \(i\!:\!j,\) or more exactly, \(m_{ij} = 1,\!\) is taken to say that \(i\!\) is a marker for \(j.\!\) This is the mode of reading that we call "multiplying on the left".
In the algebraic, permutational, or transformational contexts of application, however, Peirce converts to the alternative mode of reading, although still calling \(i\!\) the relate and \(j\!\) the correlate, the elementary relative \(i\!:\!j\) now means that \(i\!\) gets changed into \(j.\!\) In this scheme of reading, the transformation \(a\!:\!b + b\!:\!c + c\!:\!a\) is a permutation of the aggregate \(\mathbf{1} = a + b + c,\) or what we would now call the set \(\{ a, b, c \},\!\) in particular, it is the permutation that is otherwise notated as follows:
\(\begin{Bmatrix}
a & b & c
\\
b & c & a
\end{Bmatrix}\)
|
This is consistent with the convention that Peirce uses in the paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324–327).
Note 16
We've been exploring the applications of a certain technique for clarifying abstruse concepts, a rough-cut version of the pragmatic maxim that I've been accustomed to refer to as the operationalization of ideas. The basic idea is to replace the question of What it is, which modest people comprehend is far beyond their powers to answer definitively any time soon, with the question of What it does, which most people know at least a modicum about.
In the case of regular representations of groups we found a non-plussing surplus of answers to sort our way through. So let us track back one more time to see if we can learn any lessons that might carry over to more realistic cases.
Here is is the operation table of \(V_4\!\) once again:
\(\text{Klein Four-Group}~ V_4\)
\(\cdot\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
A group operation table is really just a device for recording a certain 3-adic relation, to be specific, the set of triples of the form \((x, y, z)\!\) satisfying the equation \(x \cdot y = z.\)
In the case of \(V_4 = (G, \cdot),\) where \(G\!\) is the underlying set \(\{ \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h} \},\) we have the 3-adic relation \(L(V_4) \subseteq G \times G \times G\) whose triples are listed below:
\(\begin{matrix}
(\operatorname{e}, \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{e}) &
(\operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{f}) &
(\operatorname{e}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{g}) &
(\operatorname{e}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{h})
\\[6pt]
(\operatorname{f}, \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}) &
(\operatorname{f}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{e}) &
(\operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h}) &
(\operatorname{f}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{g})
\\[6pt]
(\operatorname{g}, \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{g}) &
(\operatorname{g}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{h}) &
(\operatorname{g}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{e}) &
(\operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{f})
\\[6pt]
(\operatorname{h}, \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{h}) &
(\operatorname{h}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}) &
(\operatorname{h}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{f}) &
(\operatorname{h}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{e})
\end{matrix}\)
|
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation \(L \subseteq G^3\) is actually a function \(L : G \times G \to G.\) It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations. Since we have a function of the type \(L : G \times G \to G,\) we can define a couple of substitution operators:
1.
|
\(\operatorname{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((\underline{~~}, y),\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((x, y)\!\) that evaluates to \(xy.\!\)
|
2.
|
\(\operatorname{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((y, \underline{~~}),\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((y, x)\!\) that evaluates to \(yx.\!\)
|
In (1) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((\underline{~~}, y),\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((\underline{~~}, y)\) into \(xy,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : xy) ~|~ y \in G \}.\) The pairs \((y : xy)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run across the top margin. This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular ante-representation:
\(\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
\end{matrix}\)
|
In (2) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((y, \underline{~~}),\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((y, \underline{~~})\) into \(yx,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : yx) ~|~ y \in G \}.\) The pairs \((y : yx)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the top margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run down the left margin. This aspect of pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular post-representation:
\(\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
\end{matrix}\)
|
If the ante-rep looks the same as the post-rep, now that I'm writing them in the same dialect, that is because \(V_4\!\) is abelian (commutative), and so the two representations have the very same effects on each point of their bearing.
Note 17
So long as we're in the neighborhood, we might as well take in some more of the sights, for instance, the smallest example of a non-abelian (non-commutative) group. This is a group of six elements, say, \(G = \{ \operatorname{e}, \operatorname{f}, \operatorname{g}, \operatorname{h}, \operatorname{i}, \operatorname{j} \},\!\) with no relation to any other employment of these six symbols being implied, of course, and it can be most easily represented as the permutation group on a set of three letters, say, \(X = \{ a, b, c \},\!\) usually notated as \(G = \operatorname{Sym}(X)\) or more abstractly and briefly, as \(\operatorname{Sym}(3)\) or \(S_3.\!\) The next Table shows the intended correspondence between abstract group elements and the permutation or substitution operations in \(\operatorname{Sym}(X).\)
\(\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \operatorname{Sym} \{ a, b, c \}\)
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{i}\)
|
\(\operatorname{j}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
a & b & c
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
c & a & b
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
b & c & a
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
a & c & b
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
c & b & a
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
b & a & c
\end{matrix}\)
|
Here is the operation table for \(S_3,\!\) given in abstract fashion:
Symmetric Group S_3
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| ^ |
| e / \ e |
| / \ |
| / e \ |
| f / \ / \ f |
| / \ / \ |
| / f \ f \ |
| g / \ / \ / \ g |
| / \ / \ / \ |
| / g \ g \ g \ |
| h / \ / \ / \ / \ h |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| / h \ e \ e \ h \ |
| i / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ i |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| / i \ i \ f \ j \ i \ |
| j / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ j |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| ( j \ j \ j \ i \ h \ j ) |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ h \ h \ e \ j \ i / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ i \ g \ f \ h / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ f \ e \ g / |
| \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / |
| \ g \ f / |
| \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / |
| \ e / |
| \ / |
| \ / |
| v |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
|
By the way, we will meet with the symmetric group \(S_3\!\) again when we return to take up the study of Peirce's early paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324–327), and also his late unpublished work "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902) (CP 4.227–323), with particular reference to the section that treats of "Trichotomic Mathematics" (CP 4.307–323).
Note 18
By way of collecting a short-term pay-off for all the work that we did on the regular representations of the Klein 4-group \(V_4,\!\) let us write out as quickly as possible in relative form a minimal budget of representations for the symmetric group on three letters, \(\operatorname{Sym}(3).\) After doing the usual bit of compare and contrast among the various representations, we will have enough concrete material beneath our abstract belts to tackle a few of the presently obscured details of Peirce's early "Algebra + Logic" papers.
Writing the permutations or substitutions of \(\operatorname{Sym} \{ a, b, c \}\) in relative form generates what is generally thought of as a natural representation of \(S_3.\!\)
\(\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
& = & a\!:\!a
& + & b\!:\!b
& + & c\!:\!c
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & a\!:\!c
& + & b\!:\!a
& + & c\!:\!b
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & a\!:\!b
& + & b\!:\!c
& + & c\!:\!a
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & a\!:\!a
& + & b\!:\!c
& + & c\!:\!b
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{i}
& = & a\!:\!c
& + & b\!:\!b
& + & c\!:\!a
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{j}
& = & a\!:\!b
& + & b\!:\!a
& + & c\!:\!c
\end{matrix}\)
|
I have without stopping to think about it written out this natural representation of \(S_3\!\) in the style that comes most naturally to me, to wit, the "right" way, whereby an ordered pair configured as \(x\!:\!y\) constitutes the turning of \(x\!\) into \(y.\!\) It is possible that the next time we check in with CSP we will have to adjust our sense of direction, but that will be an easy enough bridge to cross when we come to it.
Note 19
To construct the regular representations of \(S_3,\!\) we begin with the data of its operation table:
Symmetric Group S_3
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| ^ |
| e / \ e |
| / \ |
| / e \ |
| f / \ / \ f |
| / \ / \ |
| / f \ f \ |
| g / \ / \ / \ g |
| / \ / \ / \ |
| / g \ g \ g \ |
| h / \ / \ / \ / \ h |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| / h \ e \ e \ h \ |
| i / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ i |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| / i \ i \ f \ j \ i \ |
| j / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ j |
| / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| ( j \ j \ j \ i \ h \ j ) |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ h \ h \ e \ j \ i / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ i \ g \ f \ h / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| \ f \ e \ g / |
| \ / \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / \ / |
| \ g \ f / |
| \ / \ / |
| \ / \ / |
| \ e / |
| \ / |
| \ / |
| v |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
|
Just by way of staying clear about what we are doing, let's return to the recipe that we worked out before:
It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic relation \(L \subseteq G^3\) is actually a function \(L : G \times G \to G.\) It is from this functional perspective that we can see an easy way to derive the two regular representations.
Since we have a function of the type \(L : G \times G \to G,\) we can define a couple of substitution operators:
1.
|
\(\operatorname{Sub}(x, (\underline{~~}, y))\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((\underline{~~}, y),\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((x, y)\!\) that evaluates to \(xy.\!\)
|
2.
|
\(\operatorname{Sub}(x, (y, \underline{~~}))\) puts any specified \(x\!\) into the empty slot of the rheme \((y, \underline{~~}),\) with the effect of producing the saturated rheme \((y, x)\!\) that evaluates to \(yx.\!\)
|
In (1) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((\underline{~~}, y),\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((\underline{~~}, y)\) into \(xy,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : xy) ~|~ y \in G \}.\) The pairs \((y : xy)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) from the left margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run along the right margin. This produces the regular ante-representation of \(S_3,\!\) like so:
\(\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
\operatorname{e}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{i}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{j}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
\end{array}\)
|
In (2) we consider the effects of each \(x\!\) in its practical bearing on contexts of the form \((y, \underline{~~}),\) as \(y\!\) ranges over \(G,\!\) and the effects are such that \(x\!\) takes \((y, \underline{~~})\) into \(yx,\!\) for \(y\!\) in \(G,\!\) all of which is notated as \(x = \{ (y : yx) ~|~ y \in G \}.\) The pairs \((y : yx)\!\) can be found by picking an \(x\!\) on the right margin of the group operation table and considering its effects on each \(y\!\) in turn as these run along the left margin. This produces the regular post-representation of \(S_3,\!\) like so:
\(\begin{array}{*{13}{c}}
\operatorname{e}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{i}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{j}
& = & \operatorname{e}\!:\!\operatorname{j}
& + & \operatorname{f}\!:\!\operatorname{i}
& + & \operatorname{g}\!:\!\operatorname{h}
& + & \operatorname{h}\!:\!\operatorname{g}
& + & \operatorname{i}\!:\!\operatorname{f}
& + & \operatorname{j}\!:\!\operatorname{e}
\end{array}\)
|
If the ante-rep looks different from the post-rep, it is just as it should be, as \(S_3\!\) is non-abelian (non-commutative), and so the two representations differ in the details of their practical effects, though, of course, being representations of the same abstract group, they must be isomorphic.
Note 20
|
the way of heaven and earth
is to be long continued
in their operation
without stopping
|
|
— i ching, hexagram 32
|
The Reader may be wondering what happened to the announced subject of Dynamics And Logic. What happened was a bit like this:
We made the observation that the shift operators \(\{ \operatorname{E}_{ij} \}\) form a transformation group that acts on the set of propositions of the form \(f : \mathbb{B} \times \mathbb{B} \to \mathbb{B}.\) Group theory is a very attractive subject, but it did not draw us so far from our intended course as one might initially think. For one thing, groups, especially the groups that are named after the Norwegian mathematician Marius Sophus Lie (1842–1899), have turned out to be of critical utility in the solution of differential equations. For another thing, group operations provide us with an ample supply of triadic relations that have been extremely well-studied over the years, and thus they give us no small measure of useful guidance in the study of sign relations, another brand of 3-adic relations that have significance for logical studies, and in our acquaintance with which we have barely begun to break the ice. Finally, I couldn't resist taking up the links between group representations, amounting to the very archetypes of logical models, and the pragmatic maxim.
Note 21
We've seen a couple of groups, \(V_4\!\) and \(S_3,\!\) represented in various ways, and we've seen their representations presented in a variety of different manners. Let us look at one other stylistic variant for presenting a representation that is frequently seen, the so-called matrix representation of a group.
Recalling the manner of our acquaintance with the symmetric group \(S_3,\!\) we began with the bigraph (bipartite graph) picture of its natural representation as the set of all permutations or substitutions on the set \(X = \{ a, b, c \}.\!\)
\(\text{Permutation Substitutions in}~ \operatorname{Sym} \{ a, b, c \}\)
\(\operatorname{e}\)
|
\(\operatorname{f}\)
|
\(\operatorname{g}\)
|
\(\operatorname{h}\)
|
\(\operatorname{i}\)
|
\(\operatorname{j}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
a & b & c
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
c & a & b
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
b & c & a
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
a & c & b
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
c & b & a
\end{matrix}\)
|
\(\begin{matrix}
a & b & c
\\[3pt]
\downarrow & \downarrow & \downarrow
\\[6pt]
b & a & c
\end{matrix}\)
|
These permutations were then converted to relative form as logical sums of elementary relatives:
\(\begin{matrix}
\operatorname{e}
& = & a\!:\!a
& + & b\!:\!b
& + & c\!:\!c
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{f}
& = & a\!:\!c
& + & b\!:\!a
& + & c\!:\!b
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{g}
& = & a\!:\!b
& + & b\!:\!c
& + & c\!:\!a
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{h}
& = & a\!:\!a
& + & b\!:\!c
& + & c\!:\!b
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{i}
& = & a\!:\!c
& + & b\!:\!b
& + & c\!:\!a
\\[4pt]
\operatorname{j}
& = & a\!:\!b
& + & b\!:\!a
& + & c\!:\!c
\end{matrix}\)
|
From this relational representation of Sym {a, b, c} ~=~ S_3,
one easily derives a "linear representation", regarding each
permutation as a linear transformation that maps the elements
of a suitable vector space into each other, and representing
each of these linear transformations by means of a matrix,
resulting in the following set of matrices for the group:
Table 21. Matrix Representations of the Permutations in S_3
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
| | | | | | |
| e | f | g | h | i | j |
| | | | | | |
o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o
| | | | | | |
| 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 |
| 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 |
| 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 |
| | | | | | |
o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o
The key to the mysteries of these matrices is revealed by
observing that their coefficient entries are arrayed and
overlayed on a place mat that's marked like so:
o-----o-----o-----o
| a:a | a:b | a:c |
o-----o-----o-----o
| b:a | b:b | b:c |
o-----o-----o-----o
| c:a | c:b | c:c |
o-----o-----o-----o
Note 22
It would be good to summarize, in rough but intuitive terms,
the outlook on differential logic that we have reached so far.
We've been considering a class of operators on universes
of discourse, each of which takes us from considering one
universe of discourse, X%, to considering a larger universe
of discourse, EX%.
Each of these operators, in broad terms having the form
W : X% -> EX%, acts on each proposition f : X -> B of the
source universe X% to produce a proposition Wf : EX -> B
of the target universe EX%.
The two main operators that we have worked with up to this
point are the enlargement or shift operator E : X% -> EX%
and the difference operator D : X% -> EX%.
E and D take a proposition in X%, that is, a proposition f : X -> B
that is said to be "about" the subject matter of X, and produce the
extended propositions Ef, Df : EX -> B, which may be interpreted as
being about specified collections of changes that might occur in X.
Here we have need of visual representations,
some array of concrete pictures to anchor our
more earthy intuitions and to help us keep our
wits about us before we try to climb any higher
into the ever more rarefied air of abstractions.
One good picture comes to us by way of the "field" concept.
Given a space X, a "field" of a specified type Y over X is
formed by assigning to each point of X an object of type Y.
If that sounds like the same thing as a function from X to
the space of things of type Y -- it is -- but it does seem
helpful to vary the mental images and to take advantage of
the figures of speech that spring to mind under the emblem
of this field idea.
In the field picture, a proposition f : X -> B becomes
a "scalar" field, that is, a field of values in B, or
a "field of model indications" (FOMI).
Let us take a moment to view an old proposition
in this new light, for example, the conjunction
pq : X -> B that is depicted in Figure 22-a.
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| |
| o-------------o o-------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / o \ |
| / /%\ \ |
| / /%%%\ \ |
| o o%%%%%o o |
| | |%%%%%| | |
| | P |%%%%%| Q | |
| | |%%%%%| | |
| o o%%%%%o o |
| \ \%%%/ / |
| \ \%/ / |
| \ o / |
| \ / \ / |
| o-------------o o-------------o |
| |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
| f = p q |
o-------------------------------------------------o
Figure 22-a. Conjunction pq : X -> B
Each of the operators E, D : X% -> EX% takes us from considering
propositions f : X -> B, here viewed as "scalar fields" over X,
to considering the corresponding "differential fields" over X,
analogous to what are usually called "vector fields" over X.
The structure of these differential fields can be described this way.
To each point of X there is attached an object of the following type:
a proposition about changes in X, that is, a proposition g : dX -> B.
In this frame, if X% is the universe that is generated by the set of
coordinate propositions {p, q}, then dX% is the differential universe
that is generated by the set of differential propositions {dp, dq}.
These differential propositions may be interpreted as indicating
"change in p" and "change in q", respectively.
A differential operator W, of the first order sort that we have
been considering, takes a proposition f : X -> B and gives back
a differential proposition Wf: EX -> B.
In the field view, we see the proposition f : X -> B as a scalar field
and we see the differential proposition Wf: EX -> B as a vector field,
specifically, a field of propositions about contemplated changes in X.
The field of changes produced by E on pq is shown in Figure 22-b.
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| |
| o-------------o o-------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / /%\ \ |
| / /%%%\ \ |
| o o.->-.o o |
| | p(q)(dp)dq |%\%/%| (p)q dp(dq) | |
| | o---------------|->o<-|---------------o | |
| | |%%^%%| | |
| o o%%|%%o o |
| \ \%|%/ / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ o / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------o | o-------------o |
| | |
| | |
| | |
| o |
| (p)(q) dp dq |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
| f = p q |
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| Ef = p q (dp)(dq) |
| |
| + p (q) (dp) dq |
| |
| + (p) q dp (dq) |
| |
| + (p)(q) dp dq |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
Figure 22-b. Enlargement E[pq] : EX -> B
The differential field E[pq] specifies the changes
that need to be made from each point of X in order
to reach one of the models of the proposition pq,
that is, in order to satisfy the proposition pq.
The field of changes produced by D on pq is shown in Figure 22-c.
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| |
| o-------------o o-------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / /%\ \ |
| / /%%%\ \ |
| o o%%%%%o o |
| | (dp)dq |%%%%%| dp(dq) | |
| | o<--------------|->o<-|-------------->o | |
| | |%%^%%| | |
| o o%%|%%o o |
| \ \%|%/ / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ o / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------o | o-------------o |
| | |
| | |
| v |
| o |
| dp dq |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
| f = p q |
o-------------------------------------------------o
| |
| Df = p q ((dp)(dq)) |
| |
| + p (q) (dp) dq |
| |
| + (p) q dp (dq) |
| |
| + (p)(q) dp dq |
| |
o-------------------------------------------------o
Figure 22-c. Difference D[pq] : EX -> B
The differential field D[pq] specifies the changes
that need to be made from each point of X in order
to feel a change in the felt value of the field pq.
Note 23
I want to continue developing the basic tools of differential logic,
which arose out of many years of thinking about the connections
between dynamics and logic -- those there are and those there
ought to be -- but I also wanted to give some hint of the
applications that have motivated this work all along.
One of these applications is to cybernetic systems,
whether we see these systems as agents or cultures,
individuals or species, organisms or organizations.
A cybernetic system has goals and actions for reaching them.
It has a state space X, giving us all of the states that the
system can be in, plus it has a goal space G c X, the set of
states that the system "likes" to be in, in other words, the
distinguished subset of possible states where the system is
regarded as living, surviving, or thriving, depending on the
type of goal that one has in mind for the system in question.
As for actions, there is to begin with the full set !T! of all
possible actions, each of which is a transformation of the form
T : X -> X, but a given cybernetic system will most likely have
but a subset of these actions available to it at any given time.
And even if we begin by thinking of actions in very general and
very global terms, as arbitrarily complex transformations acting
on the whole state space X, we quickly find a need to analyze and
approximate them in terms of simple transformations acting locally.
The preferred measure of "simplicity" will of course vary from one
paradigm of research to another.
A generic enough picture at this stage of the game, and one that will
remind us of these fundamental features of the cybernetic system even
as things get far more complex, is afforded by Figure 23.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| / \ |
| o o |
| | | |
| | | |
| | | |
| | G | |
| | | |
| | | |
| | | |
| o o |
| \ / |
| \ / |
| \ T / |
| \ o<------------/-------------o |
| \ / |
| \ / |
| \ / |
| o-------------------o |
| |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 23. Elements of a Cybernetic System
Note 24
Now that we've introduced the field picture for thinking about
propositions and their analytic series, a very pleasing way of
picturing the relationship among a proposition f : X -> B, its
enlargement or shift map Ef : EX -> B, and its difference map
Df : EX -> B can now be drawn.
To illustrate this possibility, let's return to the differential
analysis of the conjunctive proposition f<p, q> = pq, giving the
development a slightly different twist at the appropriate point.
Figure 24-1 shows the proposition pq once again, which we now view
as a scalar field, in effect, a potential "plateau" of elevation 1
over the shaded region, with an elevation of 0 everywhere else.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / o \ |
| / /%\ \ |
| / /%%%\ \ |
| / /%%%%%\ \ |
| / /%%%%%%%\ \ |
| / /%%%%%%%%%\ \ |
| o o%%%%%%%%%%%o o |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| | P |%%%%%%%%%%%| Q | |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| | |%%%%%%%%%%%| | |
| o o%%%%%%%%%%%o o |
| \ \%%%%%%%%%/ / |
| \ \%%%%%%%/ / |
| \ \%%%%%/ / |
| \ \%%%/ / |
| \ \%/ / |
| \ o / |
| \ / \ / |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 24-1. Proposition pq : X -> B
Given any proposition f : X -> B, the "tacit extension" of f to EX
is notated !e!f : EX -> B and defined by the equation !e!f = f, so
it's really just the same proposition living in a bigger universe.
Tacit extensions formalize the intuitive idea that a new function
is related to an old function in such a way that it obeys the same
constraints on the old variables, with a "don't care" condition on
the new variables.
Figure 24-2 illustrates the "tacit extension" of the proposition
or scalar field f = pq : X -> B to give the extended proposition
or differential field that we notate as !e!f = !e![pq] : EX -> B.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| o o (dp) (dq) o o |
| | | o-->--o | | |
| | | \ / | | |
| | (dp) dq | \ / | dp (dq) | |
| | o<-----------------o----------------->o | |
| | | | | | |
| | | | | | |
| | | | | | |
| o o | o o |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ | / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------------o | o-------------------o |
| | |
| dp | dq |
| | |
| v |
| o |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 24-2. Tacit Extension !e![pq] : EX -> B
Thus we have a pictorial way of visualizing the following data:
!e![pq]
=
p q . dp dq
+
p q . dp (dq)
+
p q . (dp) dq
+
p q . (dp)(dq)
Note 25
Staying with the example pq : X -> B, Figure 25-1 shows
the enlargement or shift map E[pq] : EX -> B in the same
style of differential field picture that we drew for the
tacit extension !e![pq] : EX -> B.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| o o (dp) (dq) o o |
| | | o-->--o | | |
| | | \ / | | |
| | (dp) dq | \ / | dp (dq) | |
| | o----------------->o<-----------------o | |
| | | ^ | | |
| | | | | | |
| | | | | | |
| o o | o o |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ | / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------------o | o-------------------o |
| | |
| dp | dq |
| | |
| | |
| o |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 25-1. Enlargement E[pq] : EX -> B
A very important conceptual transition has just occurred here,
almost tacitly, as it were. Generally speaking, having a set
of mathematical objects of compatible types, in this case the
two differential fields !e!f and Ef, both of the type EX -> B,
is very useful, because it allows us to consider these fields
as integral mathematical objects that can be operated on and
combined in the ways that we usually associate with algebras.
In this case one notices that the tacit extension !e!f and the
enlargement Ef are in a certain sense dual to each other, with
!e!f indicating all of the arrows out of the region where f is
true, and with Ef indicating all of the arrows into the region
where f is true. The only arc that they have in common is the
no-change loop (dp)(dq) at pq. If we add the two sets of arcs
mod 2, then the common loop drops out, leaving the 6 arrows of
D[pq] = !e![pq] + E[pq] that are illustrated in Figure 25-2.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| o o o o |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
| | (dp) dq | | dp (dq) | |
| | o<---------------->o<---------------->o | |
| | | ^ | | |
| | | | | | |
| | | | | | |
| o o | o o |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ | / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------------o | o-------------------o |
| | |
| dp | dq |
| | |
| v |
| o |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 25-2. Difference Map D[pq] : EX -> B
The differential features of D[pq] may be collected cell by cell of
the underlying universe X% = [p, q] to give the following expansion:
D[pq]
=
p q . ((dp)(dq))
+
p (q) . (dp) dq
+
(p) q . dp (dq)
+
(p)(q) . dp dq
Note 26
If we follow the classical line that singles out linear functions
as ideals of simplicity, then we may complete the analytic series
of the proposition f = pq : X -> B in the following way.
Figure 26-1 shows the differential proposition df = d[pq] : EX -> B
that we get by extracting the cell-wise linear approximation to the
difference map Df = D[pq] : EX -> B. This is the logical analogue
of what would ordinarily be called 'the' differential of pq, but
since I've been attaching the adjective "differential" to just
about everything in sight, the distinction tends to be lost.
For the time being, I'll resort to using the alternative
name "tangent map" for df.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / o \ \ |
| / / ^ ^ \ \ |
| o o / \ o o |
| | | / \ | | |
| | | / \ | | |
| | |/ \| | |
| | (dp)/ dq dp \(dq) | |
| | /| |\ | |
| | / | | \ | |
| | / | | \ | |
| o / o o \ o |
| \ v \ dp dq / v / |
| \ o<--------------------->o / |
| \ \ / / |
| \ \ / / |
| \ \ / / |
| \ o / |
| \ / \ / |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 26-1. Differential or Tangent d[pq] : EX -> B
Just to be clear about what's being indicated here,
it's a visual way of specifying the following data:
d[pq]
=
p q . (dp, dq)
+
p (q) . dq
+
(p) q . dp
+
(p)(q) . 0
To understand the extended interpretations, that is,
the conjunctions of basic and differential features
that are being indicated here, it may help to note
the following equivalences:
(dp, dq) = dp + dq = dp(dq) + (dp)dq
dp = dp dq + dp(dq)
dq = dp dq + (dp)dq
Capping the series that analyzes the proposition pq
in terms of succeeding orders of linear propositions,
Figure 26-2 shows the remainder map r[pq] : EX -> B,
that happens to be linear in pairs of variables.
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
| |
| X |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o |
| / \ / \ |
| / P o Q \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| / / \ \ |
| o o o o |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
| | | dp dq | | |
| | o<------------------------------->o | |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
| | | o | | |
| o o ^ o o |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \ | / / |
| \ \|/ / |
| \ dp | dq / |
| \ /|\ / |
| o-------------------o | o-------------------o |
| | |
| | |
| | |
| v |
| o |
| |
o---------------------------------------------------------------------o
Figure 26-2. Remainder r[pq] : EX -> B
Reading the arrows off the map produces the following data:
r[pq]
=
p q . dp dq
+
p (q) . dp dq
+
(p) q . dp dq
+
(p)(q) . dp dq
In short, r[pq] is a constant field,
having the value dp dq at each cell.
A more detailed presentation of Differential Logic can be found here:
DLOG D. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-May/thread.html#478
DLOG D. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-June/thread.html#553
DLOG D. http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-June/thread.html#571
Document History
Ontology List (Apr–Jul 2002)
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04040.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04041.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04045.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04046.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04047.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04048.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04052.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04054.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04055.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04067.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04068.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04069.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04070.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04072.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04073.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04074.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04077.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04079.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04080.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04268.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04269.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04272.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04273.html
- http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04290.html
Inquiry List (May & Jul 2004)
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001400.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001401.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001402.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001403.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001404.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001405.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001406.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001407.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001408.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001410.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001411.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001412.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001413.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001415.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001416.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001418.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001419.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001420.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001421.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001422.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001423.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001424.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001685.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001686.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001687.html
- http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-July/001688.html
NKS Forum (May & Jul 2004)
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1282#post1282
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1285#post1285
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1289#post1289
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1292#post1292
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1293#post1293
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1294#post1294
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1296#post1296
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1299#post1299
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1301#post1301
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1304#post1304
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1307#post1307
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1309#post1309
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1311#post1311
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1314#post1314
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1315#post1315
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1318#post1318
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1321#post1321
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1323#post1323
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1326#post1326
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1327#post1327
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1330#post1330
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1331#post1331
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1598#post1598
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1601#post1601
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1602#post1602
- http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1603#post1603
|