Difference between revisions of "Directory talk:Jon Awbrey/Papers/Inquiry Driven Systems : Part 1"

MyWikiBiz, Author Your Legacy — Saturday November 23, 2024
Jump to navigationJump to search
Line 247: Line 247:
 
'''Note on notation.'''  When there is only one sign relation <math>L_J = L(J)</math> associated with a given interpreter <math>J</math>, it is convenient to use the following forms of abbreviation:
 
'''Note on notation.'''  When there is only one sign relation <math>L_J = L(J)</math> associated with a given interpreter <math>J</math>, it is convenient to use the following forms of abbreviation:
  
:{| cellpadding=4
+
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%"
| ''J''<sub>''OS''</sub>
+
|
| = || ''Den''(''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)
+
<math>\begin{array}{lclclclcl}
| = || ''Proj''<sub>''OS''&nbsp;</sub>''L''<sub>''J''</sub>
+
J_{OS}
| = || (''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)<sub>''OS''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{Den}(L_J)
| = || ''L''(''J'')<sub>''OS''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{proj}_{OS} L_J
|-
+
& = & (L_J)_{OS}
| ''J''<sub>''SI''</sub>
+
& = & L(J)_{OS}
| = || ''Con''(''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)
+
\\[6pt]
| = || ''Proj''<sub>''SI''&nbsp;</sub>''L''<sub>''J''</sub>
+
J_{SI}
| = || (''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)<sub>''SI''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{Con}(L_J)
| = || ''L''(''J'')<sub>''SI''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{proj}_{SI} L_J
|-
+
& = & (L_J)_{SI}
| ''J''<sub>''OI''</sub>
+
& = & L(J)_{SI}
| = || ''Int''(''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)
+
\\[6pt]
| = || ''Proj''<sub>''OI''&nbsp;</sub>''L''<sub>''J''</sub>
+
J_{OI}
| = || (''L''<sub>''J''&nbsp;</sub>)<sub>''OI''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{Int}(L_J)
| = || ''L''(''J'')<sub>''OI''</sub>
+
& = & \operatorname{proj}_{OI} L_J
 +
& = & (L_J)_{OI}
 +
& = & L(J)_{OI}
 +
\end{array}</math>
 
|}
 
|}
  

Revision as of 21:04, 14 September 2010

Work Area

1.3.4.2. Sign Relations : A Primer

To the extent that their structures and functions can be discussed at all, it is likely that all of the formal entities that are destined to develop in this approach to inquiry will be instances of a class of three-place relations called sign relations. At any rate, all of the formal structures that I have examined so far in this area have turned out to be easily converted to or ultimately grounded in sign relations. This class of triadic relations constitutes the main study of the pragmatic theory of signs, a branch of logical philosophy devoted to understanding all types of symbolic representation and communication.

There is a close relationship between the pragmatic theory of signs and the pragmatic theory of inquiry. In fact, the correspondence between the two studies exhibits so many parallels and coincidences that it is often best to treat them as integral parts of one and the same subject. In a very real sense, inquiry is the process by which sign relations come to be established and continue to evolve. In other words, inquiry, "thinking" in its best sense, "is a term denoting the various ways in which things acquire significance" (Dewey). Thus, there is an active and intricate form of cooperation that needs to be appreciated and maintained between these converging modes of investigation. Its proper character is best understood by realizing that the theory of inquiry is adapted to study the developmental aspects of sign relations, a subject which the theory of signs is specialized to treat from structural and comparative points of view.

Because the examples in this section have been artificially constructed to be as simple as possible, their detailed elaboration can run the risk of trivializing the whole theory of sign relations. Still, these examples have subtleties of their own, and their careful treatment will serve to illustrate important issues in the general theory of signs.

Imagine a discussion between two people, Ann and Bob, and attend only to that aspect of their interpretive practice that involves the use of the following nouns and pronouns: "Ann", "Bob", "I", "you".

  • The object domain of this discussion fragment is the set of two people \(\{ \text{Ann}, \text{Bob} \}\).
  • The syntactic domain or the sign system of their discussion is limited to the set of four signs \(\{ {}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{Ann} {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{Bob} {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{I} {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{you} {}^{\prime\prime} \}\).

In their discussion, Ann and Bob are not only the passive objects of nominative and accusative references but also the active interpreters of the language that they use. The system of interpretation (SOI) associated with each language user can be represented in the form of an individual three-place relation called the sign relation of that interpreter.

Understood in terms of its set-theoretic extension, a sign relation \(L\!\) is a subset of a cartesian product \(O \times S \times I\). Here, \(O, S, I\!\) are three sets that are known as the object domain, the sign domain, and the interpretant domain, respectively, of the sign relation \(L \subseteq O \times S \times I\).

In general, the three domains of a sign relation can be any sets whatsoever, but the kinds of sign relations that are contemplated in a computational framework are usually constrained to having \(I \subseteq S\). In this case, interpretants are just a special variety of signs, and this makes it convenient to lump signs and interpretants together into a single class called the syntactic domain. In the forthcoming examples, \(S\!\) and \(I\!\) are identical as sets, so the very same elements manifest themselves in two different roles of the sign relations in question. When it is necessary to refer to the whole set of objects and signs in the union of the domains \(O\!\), \(S\!\), \(I\!\) for a given sign relation \(L\!\), one may refer to this set as the World of \(L\!\) and write \(W = W_L = O \cup S \cup I\).

To facilitate an interest in the abstract structures of sign relations, and to keep the notations as brief as possible as the examples become more complicated, it serves to introduce the following general notations:

\(\begin{array}{ccl} O & = & \text{Object Domain} \'"`UNIQ-MathJax1-QINU`"'. Looking to the denotative aspects of the present example, various rows of the Tables specify that \(\text{A}\) uses \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{i} {}^{\prime\prime}\) to denote \(\text{A}\) and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{u} {}^{\prime\prime}\) to denote \(\text{B}\), whereas \(\text{B}\) uses \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{i} {}^{\prime\prime}\) to denote \(\text{B}\) and \({}^{\backprime\backprime} \text{u} {}^{\prime\prime}\) to denote \(\text{A}\). It is utterly amazing that even these impoverished remnants of natural language use have properties that quickly bring the usual prospects of formal semantics to a screeching halt.

The other dyadic aspects of semantics that might be considered concern the reference that a sign has to its interpretant and the reference that an interpretant has to its object. As before, either type of reference can be multiple, unique, or empty in its collection of terminal points, and both can be formalized as different types of dyadic relations that are obtained as planar projections of the triadic sign relations.

The connection that a sign makes to an interpretant is called its connotation. In the general theory of sign relations, this aspect of semantics includes the references that a sign has to affects, concepts, impressions, intentions, mental ideas, and to the whole realm of an agent's mental states and allied activities, broadly encompassing intellectual associations, emotional impressions, motivational impulses, and real conduct. This complex ecosystem of references is unlikely ever to be mapped in much detail, much less completely formalized, but the tangible warp of its accumulated mass is commonly alluded to as the connotative import of language. Given a particular sign relation \(L\), the dyadic relation that constitutes the connotative component of \(L\) is denoted \(\operatorname{Con}(L)\).

The bearing that an interpretant has toward a common object of its sign and itself has no standard name. If an interpretant is considered to be a sign in its own right, then its independent reference to an object can be taken as belonging to another moment of denotation, but this omits the mediational character of the whole transaction.

Given the service that interpretants supply in furnishing a locus for critical, reflective, and explanatory glosses on objective scenes and their descriptive texts, it is easy to regard them as annotations both of objects and of signs, but this function points in the opposite direction to what is needed in this connection. What does one call the inverse of the annotation function? More generally asked, what is the converse of the annotation relation?

In light of these considerations, I find myself still experimenting with terms to suit this last-mentioned dimension of semantics. On a trial basis, I refer to it as the ideational, the intentional, or the canonical component of the sign relation, and I provisionally refer to the reference of an interpretant sign to its object as its ideation, its intention, or its conation. Given a particular sign relation \(L\), the dyadic relation that constitutes the intentional component of \(L\) is denoted \(\operatorname{Int}(L)\).

A full consideration of the connotative and intentional aspects of semantics would force a return to difficult questions about the true nature of the interpretant sign in the general theory of sign relations. It is best to defer these issues to a later discussion. Fortunately, omission of this material does not interfere with understanding the purely formal aspects of the present example.

Formally, these new aspects of semantics present no additional problem:

The connotative component of a sign relation L can be formalized as its dyadic projection on the plane generated by the sign domain and the interpretant domain, defined as follows:

\[\operatorname{Con}(L) = \operatorname{proj}_{SI} L = L_{SI} = \{ (s, i) \in S \times I : (o, s, i) \in L ~\text{for some}~ o \in O \}\].

The intentional component of semantics for a sign relation \(L\), or its second moment of denotation, is adequately captured by its dyadic projection on the plane generated by the object domain and interpretant domain, defined as follows:

\[\operatorname{Int}(L) = \operatorname{proj}_{OI} L = L_{OI} = \{ (o, i) \in O \times I : (o, s, i) \in L ~\text{for some}~ s \in S \}\].

As it happens, the sign relations \(L_\text{A}\) and \(L_\text{B}\) in the present example are fully symmetric with respect to exchanging signs and interpretants, so all of the structure of \((L_\text{A})_{OS}\) and \((L_\text{B})_{OS}\) is merely echoed in \((L_\text{A})_{OI}\) and \((L_\text{B})_{OI}\), respectively.

Note on notation. When there is only one sign relation \(L_J = L(J)\) associated with a given interpreter \(J\), it is convenient to use the following forms of abbreviation:

\(\begin{array}{lclclclcl} J_{OS} & = & \operatorname{Den}(L_J) & = & \operatorname{proj}_{OS} L_J & = & (L_J)_{OS} & = & L(J)_{OS} \\[6pt] J_{SI} & = & \operatorname{Con}(L_J) & = & \operatorname{proj}_{SI} L_J & = & (L_J)_{SI} & = & L(J)_{SI} \\[6pt] J_{OI} & = & \operatorname{Int}(L_J) & = & \operatorname{proj}_{OI} L_J & = & (L_J)_{OI} & = & L(J)_{OI} \end{array}\)

The principal concern of this project is not with every conceivable sign relation but chiefly with those that are capable of supporting inquiry processes. In these, the relationship between the connotational and the denotational aspects of meaning is not wholly arbitrary. Instead, this relationship must be naturally constrained or deliberately designed in such a way that it:

  1. Represents the embodiment of significant properties that have objective reality in the agent's domain.
  2. Supports the achievement of particular purposes that have intentional value for the agent.

Therefore, my attention is directed mainly toward understanding the forms of correlation, coordination, and cooperation among the various components of sign relations that form the necessary conditions for carrying out coherent inquiries.