Line 1:
Line 1:
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Cactus Language}}
{{DISPLAYTITLE:Cactus Language}}
+
<pre>
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
Inquiry Driven Systems: An Inquiry Into Inquiry
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
| Document History
+
|
+
| Subject: Inquiry Driven Systems: An Inquiry Into Inquiry
+
| Contact: Jon Awbrey <jawbrey@oakland.edu>
+
| Version: Draft 8.70
+
| Created: 23 Jun 1996
+
| Revised: 06 Jan 2002
+
| Advisor: M.A. Zohdy
+
| Setting: Oakland University, Rochester, Michigan, USA
+
| Excerpt: Section 1.3.10 (Recurring Themes)
+
| Excerpt: Subsections 1.3.10.8 - 1.3.10.13
+
|
+
| http://members.door.net/arisbe/menu/library/aboutcsp/awbrey/inquiry.htm
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.8 The Cactus Patch
+
+
| Thus, what looks to us like a sphere of scientific knowledge more accurately
+
| should be represented as the inside of a highly irregular and spiky object,
+
| like a pincushion or porcupine, with very sharp extensions in certain
+
| directions, and virtually no knowledge in immediately adjacent areas.
+
| If our intellectual gaze could shift slightly, it would alter each
+
| quill's direction, and suddenly our entire reality would change.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein, "Idols", page 38.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|"Idols of Modern Science & The Reconstruction of Knowledge", pages 37-68 in:
+
|
+
| Marcus G. Raskin & Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|'New Ways of Knowing: The Sciences, Society, & Reconstructive Knowledge',
+
| Rowman & Littlefield, Totowa, NJ, 1987.
+
+
In this and the four subsections that follow, I describe a calculus for
+
representing propositions as sentences, in other words, as syntactically
+
defined sequences of signs, and for manipulating these sentences chiefly
+
in the light of their semantically defined contents, in other words, with
+
respect to their logical values as propositions. In their computational
+
representation, the expressions of this calculus parse into a class of
+
tree-like data structures called "painted cacti". This is a family of
+
graph-theoretic data structures that can be observed to have especially
+
nice properties, turning out to be not only useful from a computational
+
standpoint but also quite interesting from a theoretical point of view.
+
The rest of this subsection serves to motivate the development of this
+
calculus and treats a number of general issues that surround the topic.
+
+
In order to facilitate the use of propositions as indicator functions
+
it helps to acquire a flexible notation for referring to propositions
+
in that light, for interpreting sentences in a corresponding role, and
+
for negotiating the requirements of mutual sense between the two domains.
+
If none of the formalisms that are readily available or in common use are
+
able to meet all of the design requirements that come to mind, then it is
+
necessary to contemplate the design of a new language that is especially
+
tailored to the purpose. In the present application, there is a pressing
+
need to devise a general calculus for composing propositions, computing
+
their values on particular arguments, and inverting their indications to
+
arrive at the sets of things in the universe that are indicated by them.
+
+
For computational purposes, it is convenient to have a middle ground or
+
an intermediate language for negotiating between the koine of sentences
+
regarded as strings of literal characters and the realm of propositions
+
regarded as objects of logical value, even if this renders it necessary
+
to introduce an artificial medium of exchange between these two domains.
+
If one envisions these computations to be carried out in any organized
+
fashion, and ultimately or partially by means of the familiar sorts of
+
machines, then the strings that express these logical propositions are
+
likely to find themselves parsed into tree-like data structures at some
+
stage of the game. With regard to their abstract structures as graphs,
+
there are several species of graph-theoretic data structures that can be
+
used to accomplish this job in a reasonably effective and efficient way.
+
+
Over the course of this project, I plan to use two species of graphs:
+
+
1. "Painted And Rooted Cacti" (PARCAI).
+
+
2. "Painted And Rooted Conifers" (PARCOI).
+
+
For now, it is enough to discuss the former class of data structures,
+
leaving the consideration of the latter class to a part of the project
+
where their distinctive features are key to developments at that stage.
+
Accordingly, within the context of the current patch of discussion, or
+
until it becomes necessary to attach further notice to the conceivable
+
varieties of parse graphs, the acronym "PARC" is sufficient to indicate
+
the pertinent genus of abstract graphs that are under consideration.
+
+
By way of making these tasks feasible to carry out on a regular basis,
+
a prospective language designer is required not only to supply a fluent
+
medium for the expression of propositions, but further to accompany the
+
assertions of their sentences with a canonical mechanism for teasing out
+
the fibers of their indicator functions. Accordingly, with regard to a
+
body of conceivable propositions, one needs to furnish a standard array
+
of techniques for following the threads of their indications from their
+
objective universe to their values for the mind and back again, that is,
+
for tracing the clues that sentences provide from the universe of their
+
objects to the signs of their values, and, in turn, from signs to objects.
+
Ultimately, one seeks to render propositions so functional as indicators
+
of sets and so essential for examining the equality of sets that they can
+
constitute a veritable criterion for the practical conceivability of sets.
+
Tackling this task requires me to introduce a number of new definitions
+
and a collection of additional notational devices, to which I now turn.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.8 The Cactus Patch (cont.)
+
+
Depending on whether a formal language is called by the type of sign
+
that makes it up or whether it is named after the type of object that
+
its signs are intended to denote, one may refer to this cactus language
+
as a "sentential calculus" or as a "propositional calculus", respectively.
+
+
When the syntactic definition of the language is well enough understood,
+
then the language can begin to acquire a semantic function. In natural
+
circumstances, the syntax and the semantics are likely to be engaged in
+
a process of co-evolution, whether in ontogeny or in phylogeny, that is,
+
the two developments probably form parallel sides of a single bootstrap.
+
But this is not always the easiest way, at least, at first, to formally
+
comprehend the nature of their action or the power of their interaction.
+
+
According to the customary mode of formal reconstruction, the language
+
is first presented in terms of its syntax, in other words, as a formal
+
language of strings called "sentences", amounting to a particular subset
+
of the possible strings that can be formed on a finite alphabet of signs.
+
A syntactic definition of the "cactus language", one that proceeds along
+
purely formal lines, is carried out in the next Subsection. After that,
+
the development of the language's more concrete aspects can be seen as
+
a matter of defining two functions:
+
+
1. The first is a function that takes each sentence of the language
+
into a computational data structure, to be exact, a tree-like
+
parse graph called a "painted cactus".
+
+
2. The second is a function that takes each sentence of the language,
+
or its interpolated parse graph, into a logical proposition, in effect,
+
ending up with an indicator function as the object denoted by the sentence.
+
+
The discussion of syntax brings up a number of associated issues that
+
have to be clarified before going on. These are questions of "style",
+
that is, the sort of description, "grammar", or theory that one finds
+
available or chooses as preferable for a given language. These issues
+
are discussed in the Subsection after next (Subsection 1.3.10.10).
+
+
There is an aspect of syntax that is so schematic in its basic character
+
that it can be conveyed by computational data structures, so algorithmic
+
in its uses that it can be automated by routine mechanisms, and so fixed
+
in its nature that its practical exploitation can be served by the usual
+
devices of computation. Because it involves the transformation of signs,
+
it can be recognized as an aspect of semiotics. Since it can be carried
+
out in abstraction from meaning, it is not up to the level of semantics,
+
much less a complete pragmatics, though it does incline to the pragmatic
+
aspects of computation that are auxiliary to and incidental to the human
+
use of language. Therefore, I refer to this aspect of formal language
+
use as the "algorithmics" or the "mechanics" of language processing.
+
A mechanical conversion of the "cactus language" into its associated
+
data structures is discussed in Subsection 1.3.10.11.
+
+
In the usual way of proceeding on formal grounds, meaning is added by giving
+
each "grammatical sentence", or each syntactically distinguished string, an
+
interpretation as a logically meaningful sentence, in effect, equipping or
+
providing each abstractly well-formed sentence with a logical proposition
+
for it to denote. A semantic interpretation of the "cactus language" is
+
carried out in Subsection 1.3.10.12.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax
+
+
| Picture two different configurations of such an irregular shape, superimposed
+
| on each other in space, like a double exposure photograph. Of the two images,
+
| the only part which coincides is the body. The two different sets of quills
+
| stick out into very different regions of space. The objective reality we
+
| see from within the first position, seemingly so full and spherical,
+
| actually agrees with the shifted reality only in the body of common
+
| knowledge. In every direction in which we look at all deeply, the
+
| realm of discovered scientific truth could be quite different.
+
| Yet in each of those two different situations, we would have
+
| thought the world complete, firmly known, and rather round
+
| in its penetration of the space of possible knowledge.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein, "Idols", page 38.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|"Idols of Modern Science & The Reconstruction of Knowledge", pages 37-68 in:
+
|
+
| Marcus G. Raskin & Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|'New Ways of Knowing: The Sciences, Society, & Reconstructive Knowledge',
+
| Rowman & Littlefield, Totowa, NJ, 1987.
+
+
In this Subsection, I describe the syntax of a family of formal languages
+
that I intend to use as a sentential calculus, and thus to interpret for
+
the purpose of reasoning about propositions and their logical relations.
+
In order to carry out the discussion, I need a way of referring to signs
+
as if they were objects like any others, in other words, as the sorts of
+
things that are subject to being named, indicated, described, discussed,
+
and renamed if necessary, that can be placed, arranged, and rearranged
+
within a suitable medium of expression, or else manipulated in the mind,
+
that can be articulated and decomposed into their elementary signs, and
+
that can be strung together in sequences to form complex signs. Signs
+
that have signs as their objects are called "higher order" (HO) signs,
+
and this is a topic that demands an apt formalization, but in due time.
+
The present discussion requires a quicker way to get into this subject,
+
even if it takes informal means that cannot be made absolutely precise.
+
+
As a temporary notation, let the relationship between a particular sign z
+
and a particular object o, namely, the fact that z denotes o or the fact
+
that o is denoted by z, be symbolized in one of the following two ways:
+
+
1. z >-> o,
+
+
z den o.
+
+
2. o <-< z,
+
+
o ned z.
+
+
Now consider the following paradigm:
+
+
1. If "A" >-> Ann,
+
+
i.e. "A" den Ann,
+
+
then A = Ann,
+
+
thus "Ann" >-> A,
+
+
i.e. "Ann" den A.
+
+
2. If Bob <-< "B",
+
+
i.e. Bob ned "B",
+
+
then Bob = B,
+
+
thus B <-< "Bob",
+
+
i.e. B ned "Bob".
+
+
When I say that the sign "blank" denotes the sign " ",
+
it means that the string of characters inside the first
+
pair of quotation marks can be used as another name for
+
the string of characters inside the second pair of quotes.
+
In other words, "blank" is a HO sign whose object is " ",
+
and the string of five characters inside the first pair of
+
quotation marks is a sign at a higher level of signification
+
than the string of one character inside the second pair of
+
quotation marks. This relationship can be abbreviated in
+
either one of the following ways:
+
+
| " " <-< "blank"
+
|
+
| "blank" >-> " "
+
+
Using the raised dot "·" as a sign to mark the articulation of a
+
quoted string into a sequence of possibly shorter quoted strings,
+
and thus to mark the concatenation of a sequence of quoted strings
+
into a possibly larger quoted string, one can write:
+
+
|
+
| " " <-< "blank" = "b"·"l"·"a"·"n"·"k"
+
|
+
+
This usage allows us to refer to the blank as a type of character, and
+
also to refer any blank we choose as a token of this type, referring to
+
either of them in a marked way, but without the use of quotation marks,
+
as I just did. Now, since a blank is just what the name "blank" names,
+
it is possible to represent the denotation of the sign " " by the name
+
"blank" in the form of an identity between the named objects, thus:
+
+
|
+
| " " = blank
+
|
+
+
With these kinds of identity in mind, it is possible to extend the use of
+
the "·" sign to mark the articulation of either named or quoted strings
+
into both named and quoted strings. For example:
+
+
| " " = " "·" " = blank·blank
+
|
+
| " blank" = " "·"blank" = blank·"blank"
+
|
+
| "blank " = "blank"·" " = "blank"·blank
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
A few definitions from formal language theory are required at this point.
+
+
An "alphabet" is a finite set of signs, typically, !A! = {a_1, ..., a_n}.
+
+
A "string" over an alphabet !A! is a finite sequence of signs from !A!.
+
+
The "length" of a string is just its length as a sequence of signs.
+
A sequence of length 0 yields the "empty string", here presented as "".
+
A sequence of length k > 0 is typically presented in the concatenated forms:
+
+
s_1 s_2 ... s_(k-1) s_k,
+
+
or
+
+
s_1 · s_2 · ... · s_(k-1) · s_k,
+
+
with s_j in !A!, for all j = 1 to k.
+
+
Two alternative notations are often useful:
+
+
1. !e! = @e@ = "" = the empty string.
+
+
2. %e% = {!e!} = {""} = the language consisting of a single empty string.
+
+
The "kleene star" !A!* of alphabet !A! is the set of all strings over !A!.
+
In particular, !A!* includes among its elements the empty string !e!.
+
+
The "surplus" !A!^+ of an alphabet !A! is the set of all positive length
+
strings over !A!, in other words, everything in !A!* but the empty string.
+
+
A "formal language" !L! over an alphabet !A! is a subset !L! c !A!*.
+
If z is a string over !A! and if z is an element of !L!, then it is
+
customary to call z a "sentence" of !L!. Thus, a formal language !L!
+
is defined by specifying its elements, which amounts to saying what it
+
means to be a sentence of !L!.
+
+
One last device turns out to be useful in this connection.
+
If z is a string that ends with a sign t, then z · t^-1 is
+
the string that results by "deleting" from z the terminal t.
+
+
In this context, I make the following distinction:
+
+
1. By "deleting" an appearance of a sign,
+
I mean replacing it with an appearance
+
of the empty string "".
+
+
2. By "erasing" an appearance of a sign,
+
I mean replacing it with an appearance
+
of the blank symbol " ".
+
+
A "token" is a particular appearance of a sign.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
The informal mechanisms that have been illustrated in the immediately preceding
+
discussion are enough to equip the rest of this discussion with a moderately
+
exact description of the so-called "cactus language" that I intend to use
+
in both my conceptual and my computational representations of the minimal
+
formal logical system that is variously known to sundry communities of
+
interpretation as "propositional logic", "sentential calculus", or
+
more inclusively, "zeroth order logic" (ZOL).
+
+
The "painted cactus language" !C! is actually a parameterized
+
family of languages, consisting of one language !C!(!P!) for
+
each set !P! of "paints".
+
+
The alphabet !A! = !M! |_| !P! is the disjoint union of two sets of symbols:
+
+
1. !M! is the alphabet of "measures", the set of "punctuation marks",
+
or the collection of "syntactic constants" that is common to all
+
of the languages !C!(!P!). This set of signs is given as follows:
+
+
!M! = {m_1, m_2, m_3, m_4}
+
+
= {" ", "-(", ",", ")-"}
+
+
= {blank, links, comma, right}.
+
+
2. !P! is the "palette", the alphabet of "paints", or the collection
+
of "syntactic variables" that is peculiar to the language !C!(!P!).
+
This set of signs is given as follows:
+
+
!P! = {p_j : j in J}.
+
+
The easiest way to define the language !C!(!P!) is to indicate the general sorts
+
of operations that suffice to construct the greater share of its sentences from
+
the specified few of its sentences that require a special election. In accord
+
with this manner of proceeding, I introduce a family of operations on strings
+
of !A!* that are called "syntactic connectives". If the strings on which
+
they operate are exclusively sentences of !C!(!P!), then these operations
+
are tantamount to "sentential connectives", and if the syntactic sentences,
+
considered as abstract strings of meaningless signs, are given a semantics
+
in which they denote propositions, considered as indicator functions over
+
some universe, then these operations amount to "propositional connectives".
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
Rather than presenting the most concise description of these languages
+
right from the beginning, it serves comprehension to develop a picture
+
of their forms in gradual stages, starting from the most natural ways
+
of viewing their elements, if somewhat at a distance, and working
+
through the most easily grasped impressions of their structures,
+
if not always the sharpest acquaintances with their details.
+
+
The first step is to define two sets of basic operations on strings of !A!*.
+
+
1. The "concatenation" of one string z_1 is just the string z_1.
+
+
The "concatenation" of two strings z_1, z_2 is the string z_1 · z_2.
+
+
The "concatenation" of the k strings z_j, for j = 1 to k,
+
+
is the string of the form z_1 · ... · z_k.
+
+
2. The "surcatenation" of one string z_1 is the string "-(" · z_1 · ")-".
+
+
The "surcatenation" of two strings z_1, z_2 is "-(" · z_1 · "," · z_2 · ")-".
+
+
The "surcatenation" of k strings z_j, for j = 1 to k,
+
+
is the string of the form "-(" · z_1 · "," · ... · "," · z_k · ")-".
+
+
These definitions can be made a little more succinct by
+
defining the following sorts of generic operators on strings:
+
+
1. The "concatenation" Conc^k of the k strings z_j,
+
for j = 1 to k, is defined recursively as follows:
+
+
a. Conc^1_j z_j = z_1.
+
+
b. For k > 1,
+
+
Conc^k_j z_j = (Conc^(k-1)_j z_j) · z_k.
+
+
2. The "surcatenation" Surc^k of the k strings z_j,
+
for j = 1 to k, is defined recursively as follows:
+
+
a. Surc^1_j z_j = "-(" · z_1 · ")-".
+
+
b. For k > 1,
+
+
Surc^k_j z_j = (Surc^(k-1)_j z_j) · ")-"^(-1) · "," · z_k · ")-".
+
+
The definitions of these syntactic operations can now be organized in a slightly
+
better fashion, for both conceptual and computational purposes, by making a few
+
additional conventions and auxiliary definitions.
+
+
1. The conception of the k-place concatenation operation
+
can be extended to include its natural "prequel":
+
+
Conc^0 = "" = the empty string.
+
+
Next, the construction of the k-place concatenation can be
+
broken into stages by means of the following conceptions:
+
+
a. The "precatenation" Prec(z_1, z_2) of the two strings
+
z_1, z_2 is the string that is defined as follows:
+
+
Prec(z_1, z_2) = z_1 · z_2.
+
+
b. The "concatenation" of the k strings z_1, ..., z_k can now be
+
defined as an iterated precatenation over the sequence of k+1
+
strings that begins with the string z_0 = Conc^0 = "" and then
+
continues on through the other k strings:
+
+
i. Conc^0_j z_j = Conc^0 = "".
+
+
ii. For k > 0,
+
+
Conc^k_j z_j = Prec(Conc^(k-1)_j z_j, z_k).
+
+
2. The conception of the k-place surcatenation operation
+
can be extended to include its natural "prequel":
+
+
Surc^0 = "-()-".
+
+
Finally, the construction of the k-place surcatenation can be
+
broken into stages by means of the following conceptions:
+
+
a. A "subclause" in !A!* is a string that ends with a ")-".
+
+
b. The "subcatenation" Subc(z_1, z_2)
+
of a subclause z_1 by a string z_2 is
+
the string that is defined as follows:
+
+
Subc(z_1, z_2) = z_1 · ")-"^(-1) · "," · z_2 · ")-".
+
+
c. The "surcatenation" of the k strings z_1, ..., z_k can now be
+
defined as an iterated subcatenation over the sequence of k+1
+
strings that starts with the string z_0 = Surc^0 = "-()-" and
+
then continues on through the other k strings:
+
+
i. Surc^0_j z_j = Surc^0 = "-()-".
+
+
ii. For k > 0,
+
+
Surc^k_j z_j = Subc(Surc^(k-1)_j z_j, z_k).
+
+
Notice that the expressions Conc^0_j z_j and Surc^0_j z_j
+
are defined in such a way that the respective operators
+
Conc^0 and Surc^0 basically "ignore", in the manner of
+
constants, whatever sequences of strings z_j may be
+
listed as their ostensible arguments.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
Having defined the basic operations of concatenation and surcatenation
+
on arbitrary strings, in effect, giving them operational meaning for
+
the all-inclusive language !L! = !A!*, it is time to adjoin the
+
notion of a more discriminating grammaticality, in other words,
+
a more properly restrictive concept of a sentence.
+
+
If !L! is an arbitrary formal language over an alphabet of the sort that
+
we are talking about, that is, an alphabet of the form !A! = !M! |_| !P!,
+
then there are a number of basic structural relations that can be defined
+
on the strings of !L!.
+
+
1. z is the "concatenation" of z_1 and z_2 in !L! if and only if
+
+
z_1 is a sentence of !L!, z_2 is a sentence of !L!, and
+
+
z = z_1 · z_2.
+
+
2. z is the "concatenation" of the k strings z1, ..., z_k in !L!,
+
+
if and only if z_j is a sentence of !L!, for all j = 1 to k, and
+
+
z = Conc^k_j z_j = z_1 · ... · z_k.
+
+
3. z is the "discatenation" of z_1 by t if and only if
+
+
z_1 is a sentence of !L!, t is an element of !A!, and
+
+
z_1 = z · t.
+
+
When this is the case, one more commonly writes:
+
+
z = z_1 · t^-1.
+
+
4. z is a "subclause" of !L! if and only if
+
+
z is a sentence of !L! and z ends with a ")-".
+
+
5. z is the "subcatenation" of z_1 by z_2 if and only if
+
+
z_1 is a subclause of !L!, z_2 is a sentence of !L!, and
+
+
z = z_1 · ")-"^(-1) · "," · z_2 · ")-".
+
+
6. z is the "surcatenation" of the k strings z_1, ..., z_k in !L!,
+
+
if and only if z_j is a sentence of !L!, for all j = 1 to k, and
+
+
z = Surc^k_j z_j = "-(" · z_1 · "," · ... · "," · z_k · ")-".
+
+
The converses of these decomposition relations are tantamount to the
+
corresponding forms of composition operations, making it possible for
+
these complementary forms of analysis and synthesis to articulate the
+
structures of strings and sentences in two directions.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
The "painted cactus language" with paints in the
+
set !P! = {p_j : j in J} is the formal language
+
!L! = !C!(!P!) c !A!* = (!M! |_| !P!)* that is
+
defined as follows:
+
+
PC 1. The blank symbol m_1 is a sentence.
+
+
PC 2. The paint p_j is a sentence, for each j in J.
+
+
PC 3. Conc^0 and Surc^0 are sentences.
+
+
PC 4. For each positive integer k,
+
+
if z_1, ..., z_k are sentences,
+
+
then Conc^k_j z_j is a sentence,
+
+
and Surc^k_j z_j is a sentence.
+
+
As usual, saying that z is a sentence is just a conventional way of
+
stating that the string z belongs to the relevant formal language !L!.
+
An individual sentence of !C!(!P!), for any palette !P!, is referred to
+
as a "painted and rooted cactus expression" (PARCE) on the palette !P!,
+
or a "cactus expression", for short. Anticipating the forms that the
+
parse graphs of these PARCE's will take, to be described in the next
+
Subsection, the language !L! = !C!(!P!) is also described as the
+
set PARCE(!P!) of PARCE's on the palette !P!, more generically,
+
as the PARCE's that constitute the language PARCE.
+
+
A "bare" PARCE, a bit loosely referred to as a "bare cactus expression",
+
is a PARCE on the empty palette !P! = {}. A bare PARCE is a sentence
+
in the "bare cactus language", !C!^0 = !C!({}) = PARCE^0 = PARCE({}).
+
This set of strings, regarded as a formal language in its own right,
+
is a sublanguage of every cactus language !C!(!P!). A bare cactus
+
expression is commonly encountered in practice when one has occasion
+
to start with an arbitrary PARCE and then finds a reason to delete or
+
to erase all of its paints.
+
+
Only one thing remains to cast this description of the cactus language
+
into a form that is commonly found acceptable. As presently formulated,
+
the principle PC 4 appears to be attempting to define an infinite number
+
of new concepts all in a single step, at least, it appears to invoke the
+
indefinitely long sequences of operators, Conc^k and Surc^k, for all k > 0.
+
As a general rule, one prefers to have an effectively finite description of
+
conceptual objects, and this means restricting the description to a finite
+
number of schematic principles, each of which involves a finite number of
+
schematic effects, that is, a finite number of schemata that explicitly
+
relate conditions to results.
+
+
A start in this direction, taking steps toward an effective description
+
of the cactus language, a finitary conception of its membership conditions,
+
and a bounded characterization of a typical sentence in the language, can be
+
made by recasting the present description of these expressions into the pattern
+
of what is called, more or less roughly, a "formal grammar".
+
+
A notation in the style of "S :> T" is now introduced,
+
to be read among many others in this manifold of ways:
+
+
| S covers T
+
|
+
| S governs T
+
|
+
| S rules T
+
|
+
| S subsumes T
+
|
+
| S types over T
+
+
The form "S :> T" is here recruited for polymorphic
+
employment in at least the following types of roles:
+
+
1. To signify that an individually named or quoted string T is
+
being typed as a sentence S of the language of interest !L!.
+
+
2. To express the fact or to make the assertion that each member
+
of a specified set of strings T c !A!* also belongs to the
+
syntactic category S, the one that qualifies a string as
+
being a sentence in the relevant formal language !L!.
+
+
3. To specify the intension or to signify the intention that every
+
string that fits the conditions of the abstract type T must also
+
fall under the grammatical heading of a sentence, as indicated by
+
the type name "S", all within the target language !L!.
+
+
In these types of situation the letter "S", that signifies the type of
+
a sentence in the language of interest, is called the "initial symbol"
+
or the "sentence symbol" of a candidate formal grammar for the language,
+
while any number of letters like "T", signifying other types of strings
+
that are necessary to a reasonable account or a rational reconstruction
+
of the sentences that belong to the language, are collectively referred
+
to as "intermediate symbols".
+
+
Combining the singleton set {"S"} whose sole member is the initial symbol
+
with the set !Q! that assembles together all of the intermediate symbols
+
results in the set {"S"} |_| !Q! of "non-terminal symbols". Completing
+
the package, the alphabet !A! of the language is also known as the set
+
of "terminal symbols". In this discussion, I will adopt the convention
+
that !Q! is the set of intermediate symbols, but I will often use "q"
+
as a typical variable that ranges over all of the non-terminal symbols,
+
q in {"S"} |_| !Q!. Finally, it is convenient to refer to all of the
+
symbols in {"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A! as the "augmented alphabet" of the
+
prospective grammar for the language, and accordingly to describe
+
the strings in ({"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A!)* as the "augmented strings",
+
in effect, expressing the forms that are superimposed on a language
+
by one of its conceivable grammars. In certain settings is becomes
+
desirable to separate the augmented strings that contain the symbol
+
"S" from all other sorts of augmented strings. In these situations,
+
the strings in the disjoint union {"S"} |_| (!Q! |_| !A!)* are known
+
as the "sentential forms" of the associated grammar.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
In forming a grammar for a language, statements of the form W :> W',
+
where W and W' are augmented strings or sentential forms of specified
+
types that depend on the style of the grammar that is being sought, are
+
variously known as "characterizations", "covering rules", "productions",
+
"rewrite rules", "subsumptions", "transformations", or "typing rules".
+
These are collected together into a set !K! that serves to complete
+
the definition of the formal grammar in question.
+
+
Correlative with the use of this notation, an expression of the
+
form "T <: S", read as "T is covered by S", can be interpreted
+
as saying that T is of the type S. Depending on the context,
+
this can be taken in either one of two ways:
+
+
1. Treating "T" as a string variable, it means
+
that the individual string T is typed as S.
+
+
2. Treating "T" as a type name, it means that any
+
instance of the type T also falls under the type S.
+
+
In accordance with these interpretations, an expression like "t <: T" can be
+
read in all of the ways that one typically reads an expression like "t : T".
+
+
There are several abuses of notation that commonly tolerated in the use
+
of covering relations. The worst offense is that of allowing symbols to
+
stand equivocally either for individual strings or else for their types.
+
There is a measure of consistency to this practice, considering the fact
+
that perfectly individual entities are rarely if ever grasped by means of
+
signs and finite expressions, which entails that every appearance of an
+
apparent token is only a type of more particular tokens, and meaning in
+
the end that there is never any recourse but to the sort of discerning
+
interpretation that can decide just how each sign is intended. In view
+
of all this, I continue to permit expressions like "t <: T" and "T <: S",
+
where any of the symbols "t", "T", "S" can be taken to signify either the
+
tokens or the subtypes of their covering types.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
The combined effect of several typos in my typography
+
along with what may be a lack of faith in imagination,
+
obliges me to redo a couple of paragraphs from before.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
A notation in the style of "S :> T" is now introduced,
+
to be read among many others in this manifold of ways:
+
+
| S covers T
+
|
+
| S governs T
+
|
+
| S rules T
+
|
+
| S subsumes T
+
|
+
| S types over T
+
+
The form "S :> T" is here recruited for polymorphic
+
employment in at least the following types of roles:
+
+
1. To signify that an individually named or quoted string T is
+
being typed as a sentence S of the language of interest !L!.
+
+
2. To express the fact or to make the assertion that each member
+
of a specified set of strings T c !A!* also belongs to the
+
syntactic category S, the one that qualifies a string as
+
being a sentence in the relevant formal language !L!.
+
+
3. To specify the intension or to signify the intention that every
+
string that fits the conditions of the abstract type T must also
+
fall under the grammatical heading of a sentence, as indicated by
+
the type name "S", all within the target language !L!.
+
+
In these types of situation the letter "S", that signifies the type of
+
a sentence in the language of interest, is called the "initial symbol"
+
or the "sentence symbol" of a candidate formal grammar for the language,
+
while any number of letters like "T", signifying other types of strings
+
that are necessary to a reasonable account or a rational reconstruction
+
of the sentences that belong to the language, are collectively referred
+
to as "intermediate symbols".
+
+
Combining the singleton set {"S"} whose sole member is the initial symbol
+
with the set !Q! that assembles together all of the intermediate symbols
+
results in the set {"S"} |_| !Q! of "non-terminal symbols". Completing
+
the package, the alphabet !A! of the language is also known as the set
+
of "terminal symbols". In this discussion, I will adopt the convention
+
that !Q! is the set of intermediate symbols, but I will often use "q"
+
as a typical variable that ranges over all of the non-terminal symbols,
+
q in {"S"} |_| !Q!. Finally, it is convenient to refer to all of the
+
symbols in {"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A! as the "augmented alphabet" of the
+
prospective grammar for the language, and accordingly to describe
+
the strings in ({"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A!)* as the "augmented strings",
+
in effect, expressing the forms that are superimposed on a language
+
by one of its conceivable grammars. In certain settings is becomes
+
desirable to separate the augmented strings that contain the symbol
+
"S" from all other sorts of augmented strings. In these situations,
+
the strings in the disjoint union {"S"} |_| (!Q! |_| !A!)* are known
+
as the "sentential forms" of the associated grammar.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
For some time to come in the discussion that follows,
+
although I will continue to focus on the cactus language
+
as my principal object example, my more general purpose will
+
be to develop and to demonstrate the subject materials and the
+
technical methodology of the theory of formal languages and grammars.
+
I will do this by taking up a particular method of "stepwise refinement"
+
and using it to extract a rigorous formal grammar for the cactus language,
+
starting with little more than a rough description of the target language
+
and applying a systematic analysis to develop a sequence of increasingly
+
more effective and more exact approximations to the desired grammar.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
Employing the notion of a covering relation it becomes possible to
+
redescribe the cactus language !L! = !C!(!P!) in the following way.
+
+
Grammar 1 is something of a misnomer. It is nowhere near exemplifying
+
any kind of a standard form and it is only intended as a starting point
+
for the initiation of more respectable grammars. Such as it is, it uses
+
the terminal alphabet !A! = !M! |_| !P! that comes with the territory of
+
the cactus language !C!(!P!), it specifies !Q! = {}, in other words, it
+
employs no intermediate symbols, and it embodies the "covering set" !K!
+
as listed in the following display.
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 1
+
|
+
| !Q! = {}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> m_1 = " "
+
|
+
| 2. S :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 3. S :> Conc^0 = ""
+
|
+
| 4. S :> Surc^0 = "-()-"
+
|
+
| 5. S :> S*
+
|
+
| 6. S :> "-(" · S · ("," · S)* · ")-"
+
+
In this formulation, the last two lines specify that:
+
+
5. The concept of a sentence in !L! covers any
+
concatenation of sentences in !L!, in effect,
+
any number of freely chosen sentences that are
+
available to be concatenated one after another.
+
+
6. The concept of a sentence in !L! covers any
+
surcatenation of sentences in !L!, in effect,
+
any string that opens with a "-(", continues
+
with a sentence, possibly empty, follows with
+
a finite number of phrases of the form "," · S,
+
and closes with a ")-".
+
+
This appears to be just about the most concise description
+
of the cactus language !C!(!P!) that one can imagine, but
+
there exist a couple of problems that are commonly felt
+
to afflict this style of presentation and to make it
+
less than completely acceptable. Briefly stated,
+
these problems turn on the following properties
+
of the presentation:
+
+
1. The invocation of the kleene star operation
+
is not reduced to a manifestly finitary form.
+
+
2. The type of a sentence S is allowed to cover
+
not only itself but also the empty string.
+
+
I will discuss these issues at first in general, and especially in regard to
+
how the two features interact with one another, and then I return to address
+
in further detail the questions that they engender on their individual bases.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
In the process of developing a grammar for a language, it is possible
+
to notice a number of organizational, pragmatic, and stylistic questions,
+
whose moment to moment answers appear to decide the ongoing direction of the
+
grammar that develops and the impact of whose considerations work in tandem
+
to determine, or at least to influence, the sort of grammar that turns out.
+
The issues that I can see arising at this point I can give the following
+
prospective names, putting off the discussion of their natures and the
+
treatment of their details to the points in the development of the
+
present example where they evolve their full import.
+
+
1. The "degree of intermediate organization" in a grammar.
+
+
2. The "distinction between empty and significant strings", and thus
+
the "distinction between empty and significant types of strings".
+
+
3. The "principle of intermediate significance". This is a constraint
+
on the grammar that arises from considering the interaction of the
+
first two issues.
+
+
In responding to these issues, it is advisable at first to proceed in
+
a stepwise fashion, all the better thereby to accommodate the chances
+
of pursuing a series of parallel developments in the grammar, to allow
+
for the possibility of reversing many steps in its development, indeed,
+
to take into account the near certain necessity of having to revisit,
+
to revise, and to reverse many decisions about how to proceed toward
+
an optimal description or a satisfactory grammar for the language.
+
Doing all this means exploring the effects of various alterations
+
and innovations as independently from each other as possible.
+
+
The degree of intermediate organization in a grammar is measured by how many
+
intermediate symbols it has and by how they interact with each other by means
+
of its productions. With respect to this issue, Grammar 1 has no intermediate
+
symbols at all, !Q! = {}, and therefore remains at an ostensibly trivial degree
+
of intermediate organization. Some additions to the list of intermediate symbols
+
are practically obligatory in order to arrive at any reasonable grammar at all,
+
other inclusions appear to have a more optional character, though obviously
+
useful from the standpoints of clarity and ease of comprehension.
+
+
One of the troubles that is perceived to affect Grammar 1 is that it wastes
+
so much of the available potential for efficient description in recounting
+
over and over again the simple fact that the empty string is present in
+
the language. This arises in part from the statement that S :> S*,
+
which implies that:
+
+
S :> S* = %e% |_| S |_| S · S |_| S · S · S |_| ...
+
+
There is nothing wrong with the more expansive pan of the covered equation,
+
since it follows straightforwardly from the definition of the kleene star
+
operation, but the covering statement, to the effect that S :> S*, is not
+
necessarily a very productive piece of information, to the extent that it
+
does always tell us very much about the language that is being supposed to
+
fall under the type of a sentence S. In particular, since it implies that
+
S :> %e%, and since %e%·!L! = !L!·%e% = !L!, for any formal language !L!,
+
the empty string !e! = "" is counted over and over in every term of the union,
+
and every non-empty sentence under S appears again and again in every term of
+
the union that follows the initial appearance of S. As a result, this style
+
of characterization has to be classified as "true but not very informative".
+
If at all possible, one prefers to partition the language of interest into
+
a disjoint union of subsets, thereby accounting for each sentence under
+
its proper term, and one whose place under the sum serves as a useful
+
parameter of its character or its complexity. In general, this form
+
of description is not always possible to achieve, but it is usually
+
worth the trouble to actualize it whenever it is.
+
+
Suppose that one tries to deal with this problem by eliminating each use of
+
the kleene star operation, by reducing it to a purely finitary set of steps,
+
or by finding an alternative way to cover the sublanguage that it is used to
+
generate. This amounts, in effect, to "recognizing a type", a complex process
+
that involves the following steps:
+
+
1. Noticing a category of strings that
+
is generated by iteration or recursion.
+
+
2. Acknowledging the circumstance that the noted category
+
of strings needs to be covered by a non-terminal symbol.
+
+
3. Making a note of it by declaring and instituting
+
an explicitly and even expressively named category.
+
+
In sum, one introduces a non-terminal symbol for each type of sentence and
+
each "part of speech" or sentential component that is generated by means of
+
iteration or recursion under the ruling constraints of the grammar. In order
+
to do this one needs to analyze the iteration of each grammatical operation in
+
a way that is analogous to a mathematically inductive definition, but further in
+
a way that is not forced explicitly to recognize a distinct and separate type of
+
expression merely to account for and to recount every increment in the parameter
+
of iteration.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
Returning to the case of the cactus language, the process of recognizing an
+
iterative type or a recursive type can be illustrated in the following way.
+
The operative phrases in the simplest sort of recursive definition are its
+
initial part and its generic part. For the cactus language !C!(!P!), one
+
has the following definitions of concatenation as iterated precatenation
+
and of surcatenation as iterated subcatenation, respectively:
+
+
1. Conc^0 = "".
+
+
Conc^k_j S_j = Prec(Conc^(k-1)_j S_j, S_k).
+
+
2. Surc^0 = "-()-".
+
+
Surc^k_j S_j = Subc(Surc^(k-1)_j S_j, S_k).
+
+
In order to transform these recursive definitions into grammar rules,
+
one introduces a new pair of intermediate symbols, "Conc" and "Surc",
+
corresponding to the operations that share the same names but ignoring
+
the inflexions of their individual parameters j and k. Recognizing the
+
type of a sentence by means of the initial symbol "S", and interpreting
+
"Conc" and "Surc" as names for the types of strings that are generated
+
by concatenation and by surcatenation, respectively, one arrives at
+
the following transformation of the ruling operator definitions
+
into the form of covering grammar rules:
+
+
1. Conc :> "".
+
+
Conc :> Conc · S.
+
+
2. Surc :> "-()-".
+
+
Surc :> "-(" · S · ")-".
+
+
Surc :> Surc ")-"^(-1) · "," · S · ")-".
+
+
As given, this particular fragment of the intended grammar
+
contains a couple of features that are desirable to amend.
+
+
1. Given the covering S :> Conc, the covering rule Conc :> Conc · S
+
says no more than the covering rule Conc :> S · S. Consequently,
+
all of the information contained in these two covering rules is
+
already covered by the statement that S :> S · S.
+
+
2. A grammar rule that invokes a notion of decatenation, deletion, erasure,
+
or any other sort of retrograde production, is frequently considered to
+
be lacking in elegance, and a there is a style of critique for grammars
+
that holds it preferable to avoid these types of operations if it is at
+
all possible to do so. Accordingly, contingent on the prescriptions of
+
the informal rule in question, and pursuing the stylistic dictates that
+
are writ in the realm of its aesthetic regime, it becomes necessary for
+
us to backtrack a little bit, to temporarily withdraw the suggestion of
+
employing these elliptical types of operations, but without, of course,
+
eliding the record of doing so.
+
+
One way to analyze the surcatenation of any number of sentences is to
+
introduce an auxiliary type of string, not in general a sentence, but
+
a proper component of any sentence that is formed by surcatenation.
+
Doing this brings one to the following definition:
+
+
A "tract" is a concatenation of a finite sequence of sentences, with a
+
literal comma "," interpolated between each pair of adjacent sentences.
+
Thus, a typical tract T takes the form:
+
+
T = S_1 · "," · ... · "," · S_k.
+
+
A tract must be distinguished from the abstract sequence of sentences,
+
S_1, ..., S_k, where the commas that appear to come to mind, as if being
+
called up to separate the successive sentences of the sequence, remain as
+
partially abstract conceptions, or as signs that retain a disengaged status
+
on the borderline between the text and the mind. In effect, the types of
+
commas that appear to follow in the abstract sequence continue to exist
+
as conceptual abstractions and fail to be cognized in a wholly explicit
+
fashion, whether as concrete tokens in the object language, or as marks
+
in the strings of signs that are able to engage one's parsing attention.
+
+
Returning to the case of the painted cactus language !L! = !C!(!P!),
+
it is possible to put the currently assembled pieces of a grammar
+
together in the light of the presently adopted canons of style,
+
to arrive a more refined analysis of the fact that the concept
+
of a sentence covers any concatenation of sentences and any
+
surcatenation of sentences, and so to obtain the following
+
form of a grammar:
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 2
+
|
+
| !Q! = {"T"}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> !e!
+
|
+
| 2. S :> m_1
+
|
+
| 3. S :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 4. S :> S · S
+
|
+
| 5. S :> "-(" · T · ")-"
+
|
+
| 6. T :> S
+
|
+
| 7. T :> T · "," · S
+
+
In this rendition, a string of type T is not in general
+
a sentence itself but a proper "part of speech", that is,
+
a strictly "lesser" component of a sentence in any suitable
+
ordering of sentences and their components. In order to see
+
how the grammatical category T gets off the ground, that is,
+
to detect its minimal strings and to discover how its ensuing
+
generations gets started from these, it is useful to observe
+
that the covering rule T :> S means that T "inherits" all of
+
the initial conditions of S, namely, T :> !e!, m_1, p_j.
+
In accord with these simple beginnings it comes to parse
+
that the rule T :> T · "," · S, with the substitutions
+
T = !e! and S = !e! on the covered side of the rule,
+
bears the germinal implication that T :> ",".
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
Grammar 2 achieves a portion of its success through a higher degree of
+
intermediate organization. Roughly speaking, the level of organization
+
can be seen as reflected in the cardinality of the intermediate alphabet
+
!Q! = {"T"}, but it is clearly not explained by this simple circumstance
+
alone, since it is taken for granted that the intermediate symbols serve
+
a purpose, a purpose that is easily recognizable but that may not be so
+
easy to pin down and to specify exactly. Nevertheless, it is worth the
+
trouble of exploring this aspect of organization and this direction of
+
development a little further. Although it is not strictly necessary
+
to do so, it is possible to organize the materials of the present
+
grammar in a slightly better fashion by recognizing two recurrent
+
types of strings that appear in the typical cactus expression.
+
In doing this, one arrives at the following two definitions:
+
+
A "rune" is a string of blanks and paints concatenated together.
+
Thus, a typical rune R is a string over {m_1} |_| !P!, possibly
+
the empty string.
+
+
R in ({m_1} |_| !P!)*.
+
+
When there is no possibility of confusion, the letter "R" can be used
+
either as a string variable that ranges over the set of runes or else
+
as a type name for the class of runes. The latter reading amounts to
+
the enlistment of a fresh intermediate symbol, "R" in !Q!, as a part
+
of a new grammar for !C!(!P!). In effect, "R" affords a grammatical
+
recognition for any rune that forms a part of a sentence in !C!(!P!).
+
In situations where these variant usages are likely to be confused,
+
the types of strings can be indicated by means of expressions like
+
"r <: R" and "W <: R".
+
+
A "foil" is a string of the form "-(" · T · ")-", where T is a tract.
+
Thus, a typical foil F has the form:
+
+
F = "-(" · S_1 · "," · ... · "," · S_k · ")-".
+
+
This is just the surcatenation of the sentences S_1, ..., S_k.
+
Given the possibility that this sequence of sentences is empty,
+
and thus that the tract T is the empty string, the minimum foil
+
F is the expression "-()-". Explicitly marking each foil F that
+
is embodied in a cactus expression is tantamount to recognizing
+
another intermediate symbol, "F" in !Q!, further articulating the
+
structures of sentences and expanding the grammar for the language
+
!C!(!P!). All of the same remarks about the versatile uses of the
+
intermediate symbols, as string variables and as type names, apply
+
again to the letter "F".
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 3
+
|
+
| !Q! = {"F", "R", "T"}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> R
+
|
+
| 2. S :> F
+
|
+
| 3. S :> S · S
+
|
+
| 4. R :> !e!
+
|
+
| 5. R :> m_1
+
|
+
| 6. R :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 7. R :> R · R
+
|
+
| 8. F :> "-(" · T · ")-"
+
|
+
| 9. T :> S
+
|
+
| 10. T :> T · "," · S
+
+
In Grammar 3, the first three Rules say that a sentence (a string of type S),
+
is a rune (a string of type R), a foil (a string of type F), or an arbitrary
+
concatenation of strings of these two types. Rules 4 through 7 specify that
+
a rune R is an empty string !e! = "", a blank symbol m_1 = " ", a paint p_j,
+
for j in J, or any concatenation of strings of these three types. Rule 8
+
characterizes a foil F as a string of the form "-(" · T · ")-", where T is
+
a tract. The last two Rules say that a tract T is either a sentence S or
+
else the concatenation of a tract, a comma, and a sentence, in that order.
+
+
At this point in the succession of grammars for !C!(!P!), the explicit
+
uses of indefinite iterations, like the kleene star operator, are now
+
completely reduced to finite forms of concatenation, but the problems
+
that some styles of analysis have with allowing non-terminal symbols
+
to cover both themselves and the empty string are still present.
+
+
Any degree of reflection on this difficulty raises the general question:
+
What is a practical strategy for accounting for the empty string in the
+
organization of any formal language that counts it among its sentences?
+
One answer that presents itself is this: If the empty string belongs to
+
a formal language, it suffices to count it once at the beginning of the
+
formal account that enumerates its sentences and then to move on to more
+
interesting materials.
+
+
Returning to the case of the cactus language !C!(!P!), that is,
+
the formal language of "painted and rooted cactus expressions",
+
it serves the purpose of efficient accounting to partition the
+
language PARCE into the following couple of sublanguages:
+
+
1. The "emptily painted and rooted cactus expressions"
+
make up the language EPARCE that consists of
+
a single empty string as its only sentence.
+
In short:
+
+
EPARCE = {""}.
+
+
2. The "significantly painted and rooted cactus expressions"
+
make up the language SPARCE that consists of everything else,
+
namely, all of the non-empty strings in the language PARCE.
+
In sum:
+
+
SPARCE = PARCE \ "".
+
+
As a result of marking the distinction between empty and significant sentences,
+
that is, by categorizing each of these three classes of strings as an entity
+
unto itself and by conceptualizing the whole of its membership as falling
+
under a distinctive symbol, one obtains an equation of sets that connects
+
the three languages being marked:
+
+
SPARCE = PARCE - EPARCE.
+
+
In sum, one has the disjoint union:
+
+
PARCE = EPARCE |_| SPARCE.
+
+
For brevity in the present case, and to serve as a generic device
+
in any similar array of situations, let the symbol "S" be used to
+
signify the type of an arbitrary sentence, possibly empty, whereas
+
the symbol "S'" is reserved to designate the type of a specifically
+
non-empty sentence. In addition, let the symbol "%e%" be employed
+
to indicate the type of the empty sentence, in effect, the language
+
%e% = {""} that contains a single empty string, and let a plus sign
+
"+" signify a disjoint union of types. In the most general type of
+
situation, where the type S is permitted to include the empty string,
+
one notes the following relation among types:
+
+
S = %e% + S'.
+
+
Consequences of the distinction between empty expressions and
+
significant expressions are taken up for discussion next time.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
With the distinction between empty and significant expressions in mind,
+
I return to the grasp of the cactus language !L! = !C!(!P!) = PARCE(!P!)
+
that is afforded by Grammar 2, and, taking that as a point of departure,
+
explore other avenues of possible improvement in the comprehension of
+
these expressions. In order to observe the effects of this alteration
+
as clearly as possible, in isolation from any other potential factors,
+
it is useful to strip away the higher levels intermediate organization
+
that are present in Grammar 3, and start again with a single intermediate
+
symbol, as used in Grammar 2. One way of carrying out this strategy leads
+
on to a grammar of the variety that will be articulated next.
+
+
If one imposes the distinction between empty and significant types on
+
each non-terminal symbol in Grammar 2, then the non-terminal symbols
+
"S" and "T" give rise to the non-terminal symbols "S", "S'", "T", "T'",
+
leaving the last three of these to form the new intermediate alphabet.
+
Grammar 4 has the intermediate alphabet !Q! = {"S'", "T", "T'"}, with
+
the set !K! of covering production rules as listed in the next display.
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 4
+
|
+
| !Q! = {"S'", "T", "T'"}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> !e!
+
|
+
| 2. S :> S'
+
|
+
| 3. S' :> m_1
+
|
+
| 4. S' :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 5. S' :> "-(" · T · ")-"
+
|
+
| 6. S' :> S' · S'
+
|
+
| 7. T :> !e!
+
|
+
| 8. T :> T'
+
|
+
| 9. T' :> T · "," · S
+
+
In this version of a grammar for !L! = !C!(!P!), the intermediate type T
+
is partitioned as T = %e% + T', thereby parsing the intermediate symbol T
+
in parallel fashion with the division of its overlying type as S = %e% + S'.
+
This is an option that I will choose to close off for now, but leave it open
+
to consider at a later point. Thus, it suffices to give a brief discussion
+
of what it involves, in the process of moving on to its chief alternative.
+
+
There does not appear to be anything radically wrong with trying this
+
approach to types. It is reasonable and consistent in its underlying
+
principle, and it provides a rational and a homogeneous strategy toward
+
all parts of speech, but it does require an extra amount of conceptual
+
overhead, in that every non-trivial type has to be split into two parts
+
and comprehended in two stages. Consequently, in view of the largely
+
practical difficulties of making the requisite distinctions for every
+
intermediate symbol, it is a common convention, whenever possible, to
+
restrict intermediate types to covering exclusively non-empty strings.
+
+
For the sake of future reference, it is convenient to refer to this restriction
+
on intermediate symbols as the "intermediate significance" constraint. It can
+
be stated in a compact form as a condition on the relations between non-terminal
+
symbols q in {"S"} |_| !Q! and sentential forms W in {"S"} |_| (!Q! |_| !A!)*.
+
+
| Condition On Intermediate Significance
+
|
+
| If q :> W
+
|
+
| and W = !e!,
+
|
+
| then q = "S".
+
+
If this is beginning to sound like a monotone condition, then it is
+
not absurd to sharpen the resemblance and render the likeness more
+
acute. This is done by declaring a couple of ordering relations,
+
denoting them under variant interpretations by the same sign "<".
+
+
1. The ordering "<" on the set of non-terminal symbols,
+
q in {"S"} |_| !Q!, ordains the initial symbol "S"
+
to be strictly prior to every intermediate symbol.
+
This is tantamount to the axiom that "S" < q,
+
for all q in !Q!.
+
+
2. The ordering "<" on the collection of sentential forms,
+
W in {"S"} |_| (!Q! |_| !A!)*, ordains the empty string
+
to be strictly minor to every other sentential form.
+
This is stipulated in the axiom that !e! < W,
+
for every non-empty sentential form W.
+
+
Given these two orderings, the constraint in question
+
on intermediate significance can be stated as follows:
+
+
| Condition Of Intermediate Significance
+
|
+
| If q :> W
+
|
+
| and q > "S",
+
|
+
| then W > !e!.
+
+
Achieving a grammar that respects this convention typically requires a more
+
detailed account of the initial setting of a type, both with regard to the
+
type of context that incites its appearance and also with respect to the
+
minimal strings that arise under the type in question. In order to find
+
covering productions that satisfy the intermediate significance condition,
+
one must be prepared to consider a wider variety of calling contexts or
+
inciting situations that can be noted to surround each recognized type,
+
and also to enumerate a larger number of the smallest cases that can
+
be observed to fall under each significant type.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
With the array of foregoing considerations in mind,
+
one is gradually led to a grammar for !L! = !C!(!P!)
+
in which all of the covering productions have either
+
one of the following two forms:
+
+
| S :> !e!
+
|
+
| q :> W, with q in {"S"} |_| !Q!, and W in (!Q! |_| !A!)^+
+
+
A grammar that fits into this mold is called a "context-free" grammar.
+
The first type of rewrite rule is referred to as a "special production",
+
while the second type of rewrite rule is called an "ordinary production".
+
An "ordinary derivation" is one that employs only ordinary productions.
+
In ordinary productions, those that have the form q :> W, the replacement
+
string W is never the empty string, and so the lengths of the augmented
+
strings or the sentential forms that follow one another in an ordinary
+
derivation, on account of using the ordinary types of rewrite rules,
+
never decrease at any stage of the process, up to and including the
+
terminal string that is finally generated by the grammar. This type
+
of feature is known as the "non-contracting property" of productions,
+
derivations, and grammars. A grammar is said to have the property if
+
all of its covering productions, with the possible exception of S :> e,
+
are non-contracting. In particular, context-free grammars are special
+
cases of non-contracting grammars. The presence of the non-contracting
+
property within a formal grammar makes the length of the augmented string
+
available as a parameter that can figure into mathematical inductions and
+
motivate recursive proofs, and this handle on the generative process makes
+
it possible to establish the kinds of results about the generated language
+
that are not easy to achieve in more general cases, nor by any other means
+
even in these brands of special cases.
+
+
Grammar 5 is a context-free grammar for the painted cactus language
+
that uses !Q! = {"S'", "T"}, with !K! as listed in the next display.
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 5
+
|
+
| !Q! = {"S'", "T"}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> !e!
+
|
+
| 2. S :> S'
+
|
+
| 3. S' :> m_1
+
|
+
| 4. S' :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 5. S' :> S' · S'
+
|
+
| 6. S' :> "-()-"
+
|
+
| 7. S' :> "-(" · T · ")-"
+
|
+
| 8. T :> ","
+
|
+
| 9. T :> S'
+
|
+
| 10. T :> T · ","
+
|
+
| 11. T :> T · "," · S'
+
+
Finally, it is worth trying to bring together the advantages of these
+
diverse styles of grammar, to whatever extent that they are compatible.
+
To do this, a prospective grammar must be capable of maintaining a high
+
level of intermediate organization, like that arrived at in Grammar 2,
+
while respecting the principle of intermediate significance, and thus
+
accumulating all the benefits of the context-free format in Grammar 5.
+
A plausible synthesis of most of these features is given in Grammar 6.
+
+
| !C!(!P!). Grammar 6
+
|
+
| !Q! = {"S'", "R", "F", "T"}
+
|
+
| 1. S :> !e!
+
|
+
| 2. S :> S'
+
|
+
| 3. S' :> R
+
|
+
| 4. S' :> F
+
|
+
| 5. S' :> S' · S'
+
|
+
| 6. R :> m_1
+
|
+
| 7. R :> p_j, for each j in J
+
|
+
| 8. R :> R · R
+
|
+
| 9. F :> "-()-"
+
|
+
| 10. F :> "-(" · T · ")-"
+
|
+
| 11. T :> ","
+
|
+
| 12. T :> S'
+
|
+
| 13. T :> T · ","
+
|
+
| 14. T :> T · "," · S'
+
+
The preceding development provides a typical example of how an initially
+
effective and conceptually succinct description of a formal language, but
+
one that is terse to the point of allowing its prospective interpreter to
+
waste exorbitant amounts of energy in trying to unravel its implications,
+
can be converted into a form that is more efficient from the operational
+
point of view, even if slightly more ungainly in regard to its elegance.
+
+
The basic idea behind all of this machinery remains the same: Besides
+
the select body of formulas that are introduced as boundary conditions,
+
it merely institutes the following general rule:
+
+
| If the strings S_1, ..., S_k are sentences,
+
|
+
| then their concatenation in the form
+
|
+
| Conc^k_j S_j = S_1 · ... · S_k
+
|
+
| is a sentence,
+
|
+
| and their surcatenation in the form
+
|
+
| Surc^k_j S_j = "-(" · S_1 · "," · ... · "," · S_k · ")-"
+
|
+
| is a sentence.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.9 The Cactus Language: Syntax (cont.)
+
+
It is fitting to wrap up the foregoing developments by summarizing the
+
notion of a formal grammar that appeared to evolve in the present case.
+
For the sake of future reference and the chance of a wider application,
+
it is also useful to try to extract the scheme of a formalization that
+
potentially holds for any formal language. The following presentation
+
of the notion of a formal grammar is adapted, with minor modifications,
+
from the treatment in (DDQ, 60-61).
+
+
A "formal grammar" !G! is given by a four-tuple !G! = ("S", !Q!, !A!, !K!)
+
that takes the following form of description:
+
+
1. "S" is the "initial", "special", "start", or "sentence symbol".
+
Since the letter "S" serves this function only in a special setting,
+
its employment in this role need not create any confusion with its
+
other typical uses as a string variable or as a sentence variable.
+
+
2. !Q! = {q_1, ..., q_m} is a finite set of "intermediate symbols",
+
all distinct from "S".
+
+
3. !A! = {a_1, ..., a_n} is a finite set of "terminal symbols",
+
also known as the "alphabet" of !G!, all distinct from "S" and
+
disjoint from !Q!. Depending on the particular conception of the
+
language !L! that is "covered", "generated", "governed", or "ruled"
+
by the grammar !G!, that is, whether !L! is conceived to be a set of
+
words, sentences, paragraphs, or more extended structures of discourse,
+
it is usual to describe !A! as the "alphabet", "lexicon", "vocabulary",
+
"liturgy", or "phrase book" of both the grammar !G! and the language !L!
+
that it regulates.
+
+
4. !K! is a finite set of "characterizations". Depending on how they
+
come into play, these are variously described as "covering rules",
+
"formations", "productions", "rewrite rules", "subsumptions",
+
"transformations", or "typing rules".
+
+
To describe the elements of !K! it helps to define some additional terms:
+
+
a. The symbols in {"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A! form the "augmented alphabet" of !G!.
+
+
b. The symbols in {"S"} |_| !Q! are the "non-terminal symbols" of !G!.
+
+
c. The symbols in !Q! |_| !A! are the "non-initial symbols" of !G!.
+
+
d. The strings in ({"S"} |_| !Q! |_| !A!)* are the "augmented strings" for G.
+
+
e. The strings in {"S"} |_| (!Q! |_| !A!)* are the "sentential forms" for G.
+
+
Each characterization in !K! is an ordered pair of strings (S_1, S_2)
+
that takes the following form:
+
+
| S_1 = Q_1 · q · Q_2,
+
|
+
| S_2 = Q_1 · W · Q_2.
+
+
In this scheme, S_1 and S_2 are members of the augmented strings for !G!,
+
more precisely, S_1 is a non-empty string and a sentential form over !G!,
+
while S_2 is a possibly empty string and also a sentential form over !G!.
+
+
Here also, q is a non-terminal symbol, that is, q is in {"S"} |_| !Q!,
+
while Q_1, Q_2, and W are possibly empty strings of non-initial symbols,
+
a fact that can be expressed in the form: Q_1, Q_2, W in (!Q! |_| !A!)*.
+
+
In practice, the ordered pairs of strings in !K! are used to "derive",
+
to "generate", or to "produce" sentences of the language !L! = <!G!>
+
that is then said to be "governed" or "regulated" by the grammar !G!.
+
In order to facilitate this active employment of the grammar, it is
+
conventional to write the characterization (S_1, S_2) in either one
+
of the next two forms, where the more generic form is followed by
+
the more specific form:
+
+
| S_1 :> S_2
+
|
+
| Q_1 · q · Q_2 :> Q_1 · W · Q_2
+
+
In this usage, the characterization S_1 :> S_2 is tantamount to a grammatical
+
license to transform a string of the form Q_1 · q · Q_2 into a string of the
+
form Q1 · W · Q2, in effect, replacing the non-terminal symbol q with the
+
non-initial string W in any selected, preserved, and closely adjoining
+
context of the form Q1 · ... · Q2. Accordingly, in this application
+
the notation "S_1 :> S_2" can be read as "S_1 produces S_2" or as
+
"S_1 transforms into S_2".
+
+
An "immediate derivation" in !G! is an ordered pair (W, W')
+
of sentential forms in !G! such that:
+
+
| W = Q_1 · X · Q_2,
+
|
+
| W' = Q_1 · Y · Q_2,
+
|
+
| and (X, Y) in !K!,
+
|
+
| i.e. X :> Y in !G!.
+
+
This relation is indicated by saying that W "immediately derives" W',
+
that W' is "immediately derived" from W in !G!, and also by writing:
+
+
W ::> W'.
+
+
A "derivation" in !G! is a finite sequence (W_1, ..., W_k)
+
of sentential forms over !G! such that each adjacent pair
+
(W_j, W_(j+1)) of sentential forms in the sequence is an
+
immediate derivation in !G!, in other words, such that:
+
+
W_j ::> W_(j+1), for all j = 1 to k-1.
+
+
If there exists a derivation (W_1, ..., W_k) in !G!,
+
one says that W_1 "derives" W_k in !G!, conversely,
+
that W_k is "derivable" from W_1 in !G!, and one
+
typically summarizes the derivation by writing:
+
+
W_1 :*:> W_k.
+
+
The language !L! = !L!(!G!) = <!G!> that is "generated"
+
by the formal grammar !G! = ("S", !Q!, !A!, !K!) is the
+
set of strings over the terminal alphabet !A! that are
+
derivable from the initial symbol "S" by way of the
+
intermediate symbols in !Q! according to the
+
characterizations in K. In sum:
+
+
!L!(!G!) = <!G!> = {W in !A!* : "S" :*:> W}.
+
+
Finally, a string W is called a "word", a "sentence", or so on,
+
of the language generated by !G! if and only if W is in !L!(!G!).
+
+
Reference
+
+
| Denning, P.J., Dennis, J.B., Qualitz, J.E.,
+
|'Machines, Languages, and Computation',
+
| Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1978.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics
+
+
| As a result, we can hardly conceive of how many possibilities there are
+
| for what we call objective reality. Our sharp quills of knowledge are so
+
| narrow and so concentrated in particular directions that with science there
+
| are myriads of totally different real worlds, each one accessible from the
+
| next simply by slight alterations -- shifts of gaze -- of every particular
+
| discipline and subspecialty.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein, "Idols", page 38.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|"Idols of Modern Science & The Reconstruction of Knowledge", pages 37-68 in:
+
|
+
| Marcus G. Raskin & Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|'New Ways of Knowing: The Sciences, Society, & Reconstructive Knowledge',
+
| Rowman & Littlefield, Totowa, NJ, 1987.
+
+
This Subsection highlights an issue of "style" that arises in describing
+
a formal language. In broad terms, I use the word "style" to refer to a
+
loosely specified class of formal systems, typically ones that have a set
+
of distinctive features in common. For instance, a style of proof system
+
usually dictates one or more rules of inference that are acknowledged as
+
conforming to that style. In the present context, the word "style" is a
+
natural choice to characterize the varieties of formal grammars, or any
+
other sorts of formal systems that can be contemplated for deriving the
+
sentences of a formal language.
+
+
In looking at what seems like an incidental issue, the discussion arrives
+
at a critical point. The question is: What decides the issue of style?
+
Taking a given language as the object of discussion, what factors enter
+
into and determine the choice of a style for its presentation, that is,
+
a particular way of arranging and selecting the materials that come to
+
be involved in a description, a grammar, or a theory of the language?
+
To what degree is the determination accidental, empirical, pragmatic,
+
rhetorical, or stylistic, and to what extent is the choice essential,
+
logical, and necessary? For that matter, what determines the order
+
of signs in a word, a sentence, a text, or a discussion? All of
+
the corresponding parallel questions about the character of this
+
choice can be posed with regard to the constituent part as well
+
as with regard to the main constitution of the formal language.
+
+
In order to answer this sort of question, at any level of articulation,
+
one has to inquire into the type of distinction that it invokes, between
+
arrangements and orders that are essential, logical, and necessary and
+
orders and arrangements that are accidental, rhetorical, and stylistic.
+
As a rough guide to its comprehension, a "logical order", if it resides
+
in the subject at all, can be approached by considering all of the ways
+
of saying the same things, in all of the languages that are capable of
+
saying roughly the same things about that subject. Of course, the "all"
+
that appears in this rule of thumb has to be interpreted as a fittingly
+
qualified sort of universal. For all practical purposes, it simply means
+
"all of the ways that a person can think of" and "all of the languages
+
that a person can conceive of", with all things being relative to the
+
particular moment of investigation. For all of these reasons, the rule
+
must stand as little more than a rough idea of how to approach its object.
+
+
If it is demonstrated that a given formal language can be presented in
+
any one of several styles of formal grammar, then the choice of a format
+
is accidental, optional, and stylistic to the very extent that it is free.
+
But if it can be shown that a particular language cannot be successfully
+
presented in a particular style of grammar, then the issue of style is
+
no longer free and rhetorical, but becomes to that very degree essential,
+
necessary, and obligatory, in other words, a question of the objective
+
logical order that can be found to reside in the object language.
+
+
As a rough illustration of the difference between logical and rhetorical
+
orders, consider the kinds of order that are expressed and exhibited in
+
the following conjunction of implications:
+
+
"X => Y and Y => Z".
+
+
Here, there is a happy conformity between the logical content and the
+
rhetorical form, indeed, to such a degree that one hardly notices the
+
difference between them. The rhetorical form is given by the order
+
of sentences in the two implications and the order of implications
+
in the conjunction. The logical content is given by the order of
+
propositions in the extended implicational sequence:
+
+
X =< Y =< Z.
+
+
To see the difference between form and content, or manner and matter,
+
it is enough to observe a few of the ways that the expression can be
+
varied without changing its meaning, for example:
+
+
"Z <= Y and Y <= X".
+
+
Any style of declarative programming, also called "logic programming",
+
depends on a capacity, as embodied in a programming language or other
+
formal system, to describe the relation between problems and solutions
+
in logical terms. A recurring problem in building this capacity is in
+
bridging the gap between ostensibly non-logical orders and the logical
+
orders that are used to describe and to represent them. For instance,
+
to mention just a couple of the most pressing cases, and the ones that
+
are currently proving to be the most resistant to a complete analysis,
+
one has the orders of dynamic evolution and rhetorical transition that
+
manifest themselves in the process of inquiry and in the communication
+
of its results.
+
+
This patch of the ongoing discussion is concerned with describing a
+
particular variety of formal languages, whose typical representative
+
is the painted cactus language !L! = !C!(!P!). It is the intention of
+
this work to interpret this language for propositional logic, and thus
+
to use it as a sentential calculus, an order of reasoning that forms an
+
active ingredient and a significant component of all logical reasoning.
+
To describe this language, the standard devices of formal grammars and
+
formal language theory are more than adequate, but this only raises the
+
next question: What sorts of devices are exactly adequate, and fit the
+
task to a "T"? The ultimate desire is to turn the tables on the order
+
of description, and so begins a process of eversion that evolves to the
+
point of asking: To what extent can the language capture the essential
+
features and laws of its own grammar and describe the active principles
+
of its own generation? In other words: How well can the language be
+
described by using the language itself to do so?
+
+
In order to speak to these questions, I have to express what a grammar says
+
about a language in terms of what a language can say on its own. In effect,
+
it is necessary to analyze the kinds of meaningful statements that grammars
+
are capable of making about languages in general and to relate them to the
+
kinds of meaningful statements that the syntactic "sentences" of the cactus
+
language might be interpreted as making about the very same topics. So far
+
in the present discussion, the sentences of the cactus language do not make
+
any meaningful statements at all, much less any meaningful statements about
+
languages and their constitutions. As of yet, these sentences subsist in the
+
form of purely abstract, formal, and uninterpreted combinatorial constructions.
+
+
Before the capacity of a language to describe itself can be evaluated,
+
the missing link to meaning has to be supplied for each of its strings.
+
This calls for a dimension of semantics and a notion of interpretation,
+
topics that are taken up for the case of the cactus language !C!(!P!)
+
in Subsection 1.3.10.12. Once a plausible semantics is prescribed for
+
this language it will be possible to return to these questions and to
+
address them in a meaningful way.
+
+
The prominent issue at this point is the distinct placements of formal
+
languages and formal grammars with respect to the question of meaning.
+
The sentences of a formal language are merely the abstract strings of
+
abstract signs that happen to belong to a certain set. They do not by
+
themselves make any meaningful statements at all, not without mounting
+
a separate effort of interpretation, but the rules of a formal grammar
+
make meaningful statements about a formal language, to the extent that
+
they say what strings belong to it and what strings do not. Thus, the
+
formal grammar, a formalism that appears to be even more skeletal than
+
the formal language, still has bits and pieces of meaning attached to it.
+
In a sense, the question of meaning is factored into two parts, structure
+
and value, leaving the aspect of value reduced in complexity and subtlety
+
to the simple question of belonging. Whether this single bit of meaningful
+
value is enough to encompass all of the dimensions of meaning that we require,
+
and whether it can be compounded to cover the complexity that actually exists
+
in the realm of meaning -- these are questions for an extended future inquiry.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
Perhaps I ought to comment on the differences between the present and
+
the standard definition of a formal grammar, since I am attempting to
+
strike a compromise with several alternative conventions of usage, and
+
thus to leave certain options open for future exploration. All of the
+
changes are minor, in the sense that they are not intended to alter the
+
classes of languages that are able to be generated, but only to clear up
+
various ambiguities and sundry obscurities that affect their conception.
+
+
Primarily, the conventional scope of non-terminal symbols was expanded
+
to encompass the sentence symbol, mainly on account of all the contexts
+
where the initial and the intermediate symbols are naturally invoked in
+
the same breath. By way of compensating for the usual exclusion of the
+
sentence symbol from the non-terminal class, an equivalent distinction
+
was introduced in the fashion of a distinction between the initial and
+
the intermediate symbols, and this serves its purpose in all of those
+
contexts where the two kind of symbols need to be treated separately.
+
+
At the present point, I remain a bit worried about the motivations
+
and the justifications for introducing this distinction, under any
+
name, in the first place. It is purportedly designed to guarantee
+
that the process of derivation at least gets started in a definite
+
direction, while the real questions have to do with how it all ends.
+
The excuses of efficiency and expediency that I offered as plausible
+
and sufficient reasons for distinguishing between empty and significant
+
sentences are likely to be ephemeral, if not entirely illusory, since
+
intermediate symbols are still permitted to characterize or to cover
+
themselves, not to mention being allowed to cover the empty string,
+
and so the very types of traps that one exerts oneself to avoid at
+
the outset are always there to afflict the process at all of the
+
intervening times.
+
+
If one reflects on the form of grammar that is being prescribed here,
+
it looks as if one sought, rather futilely, to avoid the problems of
+
recursion by proscribing the main program from calling itself, while
+
allowing any subprogram to do so. But any trouble that is avoidable
+
in the part is also avoidable in the main, while any trouble that is
+
inevitable in the part is also inevitable in the main. Consequently,
+
I am reserving the right to change my mind at a later stage, perhaps
+
to permit the initial symbol to characterize, to cover, to regenerate,
+
or to produce itself, if that turns out to be the best way in the end.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
Before I leave this Subsection, I need to say a few things about
+
the manner in which the abstract theory of formal languages and
+
the pragmatic theory of sign relations interact with each other.
+
+
Formal language theory can seem like an awfully picky subject at times,
+
treating every symbol as a thing in itself the way it does, sorting out
+
the nominal types of symbols as objects in themselves, and singling out
+
the passing tokens of symbols as distinct entities in their own rights.
+
It has to continue doing this, if not for any better reason than to aid
+
in clarifying the kinds of languages that people are accustomed to use,
+
to assist in writing computer programs that are capable of parsing real
+
sentences, and to serve in designing programming languages that people
+
would like to become accustomed to use. As a matter of fact, the only
+
time that formal language theory becomes too picky, or a bit too myopic
+
in its focus, is when it leads one to think that one is dealing with the
+
thing itself and not just with the sign of it, in other words, when the
+
people who use the tools of formal language theory forget that they are
+
dealing with the mere signs of more interesting objects and not with the
+
objects of ultimate interest in and of themselves.
+
+
As a result, there a number of deleterious effects that can arise from
+
the extreme pickiness of formal language theory, arising, as is often the
+
case, when formal theorists forget the practical context of theorization.
+
It frequently happens that the exacting task of defining the membership
+
of a formal language leads one to think that this object and this object
+
alone is the justifiable end of the whole exercise. The distractions of
+
this mediate objective render one liable to forget that one's penultimate
+
interest lies always with various kinds of equivalence classes of signs,
+
not entirely or exclusively with their more meticulous representatives.
+
+
When this happens, one typically goes on working oblivious to the fact
+
that many details about what transpires in the meantime do not matter
+
at all in the end, and one is likely to remain in blissful ignorance
+
of the circumstance that many special details of language membership
+
are bound, destined, and pre-determined to be glossed over with some
+
measure of indifference, especially when it comes down to the final
+
constitution of those equivalence classes of signs that are able to
+
answer for the genuine objects of the whole enterprise of language.
+
When any form of theory, against its initial and its best intentions,
+
leads to this kind of absence of mind that is no longer beneficial in
+
all of its main effects, the situation calls for an antidotal form of
+
theory, one that can restore the presence of mind that all forms of
+
theory are meant to augment.
+
+
The pragmatic theory of sign relations is called for in settings where
+
everything that can be named has many other names, that is to say, in
+
the usual case. Of course, one would like to replace this superfluous
+
multiplicity of signs with an organized system of canonical signs, one
+
for each object that needs to be denoted, but reducing the redundancy
+
too far, beyond what is necessary to eliminate the factor of "noise" in
+
the language, that is, to clear up its effectively useless distractions,
+
can destroy the very utility of a typical language, which is intended to
+
provide a ready means to express a present situation, clear or not, and
+
to describe an ongoing condition of experience in just the way that it
+
seems to present itself. Within this fleshed out framework of language,
+
moreover, the process of transforming the manifestations of a sign from
+
its ordinary appearance to its canonical aspect is the whole problem of
+
computation in a nutshell.
+
+
It is a well-known truth, but an often forgotten fact, that nobody
+
computes with numbers, but solely with numerals in respect of numbers,
+
and numerals themselves are symbols. Among other things, this renders
+
all discussion of numeric versus symbolic computation a bit beside the
+
point, since it is only a question of what kinds of symbols are best for
+
one's immediate application or for one's selection of ongoing objectives.
+
The numerals that everybody knows best are just the canonical symbols,
+
the standard signs or the normal terms for numbers, and the process of
+
computation is a matter of getting from the arbitrarily obscure signs
+
that the data of a situation are capable of throwing one's way to the
+
indications of its character that are clear enough to motivate action.
+
+
Having broached the distinction between propositions and sentences, one
+
can see its similarity to the distinction between numbers and numerals.
+
What are the implications of the foregoing considerations for reasoning
+
about propositions and for the realm of reckonings in sentential logic?
+
If the purpose of a sentence is just to denote a proposition, then the
+
proposition is just the object of whatever sign is taken for a sentence.
+
This means that the computational manifestation of a piece of reasoning
+
about propositions amounts to a process that takes place entirely within
+
a language of sentences, a procedure that can rationalize its account by
+
referring to the denominations of these sentences among propositions.
+
+
The application of these considerations in the immediate setting is this:
+
Do not worry too much about what roles the empty string "" and the blank
+
symbol " " are supposed to play in a given species of formal languages.
+
As it happens, it is far less important to wonder whether these types
+
of formal tokens actually constitute genuine sentences than it is to
+
decide what equivalence classes it makes sense to form over all of
+
the sentences in the resulting language, and only then to bother
+
about what equivalence classes these limiting cases of sentences
+
are most conveniently taken to represent.
+
+
These concerns about boundary conditions betray a more general issue.
+
Already by this point in discussion the limits of the purely syntactic
+
approach to a language are beginning to be visible. It is not that one
+
cannot go a whole lot further by this road in the analysis of a particular
+
language and in the study of languages in general, but when it comes to the
+
questions of understanding the purpose of a language, of extending its usage
+
in a chosen direction, or of designing a language for a particular set of uses,
+
what matters above all else are the "pragmatic equivalence classes" of signs that
+
are demanded by the application and intended by the designer, and not so much the
+
peculiar characters of the signs that represent these classes of practical meaning.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
Any description of a language is bound to have alternative descriptions.
+
More precisely, a circumscribed description of a formal language, as any
+
effectively finite description is bound to be, is certain to suggest the
+
equally likely existence and the possible utility of other descriptions.
+
A single formal grammar describes but a single formal language, but any
+
formal language is described by many different formal grammars, not all
+
of which afford the same grasp of its structure, provide an equivalent
+
comprehension of its character, or yield an interchangeable view of its
+
aspects. Consequently, even with respect to the same formal language,
+
different formal grammars are typically better for different purposes.
+
+
With the distinctions that evolve among the different styles of grammar,
+
and with the preferences that different observers display toward them,
+
there naturally comes the question: What is the root of this evolution?
+
+
One dimension of variation in the styles of formal grammars can be seen
+
by treating the union of languages, and especially the disjoint union of
+
languages, as a "sum", by treating the concatenation of languages as a
+
"product", and then by distinguishing the styles of analysis that favor
+
"sums of products" from those that favor "products of sums" as their
+
canonical forms of description. If one examines the relation between
+
languages and grammars carefully enough to see the presence and the
+
influence of these different styles, and when one comes to appreciate
+
the ways that different styles of grammars can be used with different
+
degrees of success for different purposes, then one begins to see the
+
possibility that alternative styles of description can be based on
+
altogether different linguistic and logical operations.
+
+
It possible to trace this divergence of styles to an even more primitive
+
division, one that distinguishes the "additive" or the "parallel" styles
+
from the "multiplicative" or the "serial" styles. The issue is somewhat
+
confused by the fact that an "additive" analysis is typically expressed
+
in the form of a "series", in other words, a disjoint union of sets or a
+
linear sum of their independent effects. But it is easy enough to sort
+
this out if one observes the more telling connection between "parallel"
+
and "independent". Another way to keep the right associations straight
+
is to employ the term "sequential" in preference to the more misleading
+
term "serial". Whatever one calls this broad division of styles, the
+
scope and sweep of their dimensions of variation can be delineated in
+
the following way:
+
+
1. The "additive" or "parallel" styles favor "sums of products" as
+
canonical forms of expression, pulling sums, unions, co-products,
+
and logical disjunctions to the outermost layers of analysis and
+
synthesis, while pushing products, intersections, concatenations,
+
and logical conjunctions to the innermost levels of articulation
+
and generation. In propositional logic, this style leads to the
+
"disjunctive normal form" (DNF).
+
+
2. The "multiplicative" or "serial" styles favor "products of sums"
+
as canonical forms of expression, pulling products, intersections,
+
concatenations, and logical conjunctions to the outermost layers of
+
analysis and synthesis, while pushing sums, unions, co-products,
+
and logical disjunctions to the innermost levels of articulation
+
and generation. In propositional logic, this style leads to the
+
"conjunctive normal form" (CNF).
+
+
There is a curious sort of diagnostic clue, a veritable shibboleth,
+
that often serves to reveal the dominance of one mode or the other
+
within an individual thinker's cognitive style. Examined on the
+
question of what constitutes the "natural numbers", an "additive"
+
thinker tends to start the sequence at 0, while a "multiplicative"
+
thinker tends to regard it as beginning at 1.
+
+
In any style of description, grammar, or theory of a language, it is
+
usually possible to tease out the influence of these contrasting traits,
+
namely, the "additive" attitude versus the "mutiplicative" tendency that
+
go to make up the particular style in question, and even to determine the
+
dominant inclination or point of view that establishes its perspective on
+
the target domain.
+
+
In each style of formal grammar, the "multiplicative" aspect is present
+
in the sequential concatenation of signs, both in the augmented strings
+
and in the terminal strings. In settings where the non-terminal symbols
+
classify types of strings, the concatenation of the non-terminal symbols
+
signifies the cartesian product over the corresponding sets of strings.
+
+
In the context-free style of formal grammar, the "additive" aspect is
+
easy enough to spot. It is signaled by the parallel covering of many
+
augmented strings or sentential forms by the same non-terminal symbol.
+
Expressed in active terms, this calls for the independent rewriting
+
of that non-terminal symbol by a number of different successors,
+
as in the following scheme:
+
+
| q :> W_1.
+
|
+
| ... ... ...
+
|
+
| q :> W_k.
+
+
It is useful to examine the relationship between the grammatical covering
+
or production relation ":>" and the logical relation of implication "=>",
+
with one eye to what they have in common and one eye to how they differ.
+
The production "q :> W" says that the appearance of the symbol "q" in
+
a sentential form implies the possibility of exchanging it for "W".
+
Although this sounds like a "possible implication", to the extent
+
that "q implies a possible W" or that "q possibly implies W", the
+
qualifiers "possible" and "possibly" are the critical elements in
+
these statements, and they are crucial to the meaning of what is
+
actually being implied. In effect, these qualifications reverse
+
the direction of implication, yielding "q <= W" as the best
+
analogue for the sense of the production.
+
+
One way to sum this up is to say that non-terminal symbols have the
+
significance of hypotheses. The terminal strings form the empirical
+
matter of a language, while the non-terminal symbols mark the patterns
+
or the types of substrings that can be noticed in the profusion of data.
+
If one observes a portion of a terminal string that falls into the pattern
+
of the sentential form W, then it is an admissable hypothesis, according to
+
the theory of the language that is constituted by the formal grammar, that
+
this piece not only fits the type q but even comes to be generated under
+
the auspices of the non-terminal symbol "q".
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
A moment's reflection on the issue of style, giving due consideration to the
+
received array of stylistic choices, ought to inspire at least the question:
+
"Are these the only choices there are?" In the present setting, there are
+
abundant indications that other options, more differentiated varieties of
+
description and more integrated ways of approaching individual languages,
+
are likely to be conceivable, feasible, and even more ultimately viable.
+
If a suitably generic style, one that incorporates the full scope of
+
logical combinations and operations, is broadly available, then it
+
would no longer be necessary, or even apt, to argue in universal
+
terms about "which style is best", but more useful to investigate
+
how we might adapt the local styles to the local requirements.
+
The medium of a generic style would yield a viable compromise
+
between "additive" and "multiplicative" canons, and render the
+
choice between "parallel" and "serial" a false alternative,
+
at least, when expressed in the globally exclusive terms
+
that are currently most commonly adopted to pose it.
+
+
One set of indications comes from the study of machines, languages, and
+
computation, especially the theories of their structures and relations.
+
The forms of composition and decomposition that are generally known as
+
"parallel" and "serial" are merely the extreme special cases, in variant
+
directions of specialization, of a more generic form, usually called the
+
"cascade" form of combination. This is a well-known fact in the theories
+
that deal with automata and their associated formal languages, but its
+
implications do not seem to be widely appreciated outside these fields.
+
In particular, it dispells the need to choose one extreme or the other,
+
since most of the natural cases are likely to exist somewhere in between.
+
+
Another set of indications appears in algebra and category theory,
+
where forms of composition and decomposition related to the cascade
+
combination, namely, the "semi-direct product" and its special case,
+
the "wreath product", are encountered at higher levels of generality
+
than the cartesian products of sets or the direct products of spaces.
+
+
In these domains of operation, one finds it necessary to consider also
+
the "co-product" of sets and spaces, a construction that artificially
+
creates a disjoint union of sets, that is, a union of spaces that are
+
being treated as independent. It does this, in effect, by "indexing",
+
"coloring", or "preparing" the otherwise possibly overlapping domains
+
that are being combined. What renders this a "chimera" or a "hybrid"
+
form of combination is the fact that this indexing is tantamount to a
+
cartesian product of a singleton set, namely, the conventional "index",
+
"color", or "affix" in question, with the individual domain that is
+
entering as a factor, a term, or a participant in the final result.
+
+
One of the insights that arises out of Peirce's logical work is that
+
the set operations of complementation, intersection, and union, along
+
with the logical operations of negation, conjunction, and disjunction
+
that operate in isomorphic tandem with them, are not as fundamental as
+
they first appear. This is because all of them can be constructed from
+
or derived from a smaller set of operations, in fact, taking the logical
+
side of things, from either one of two "solely sufficient" operators,
+
called "amphecks" by Peirce, "strokes" by those who re-discovered them
+
later, and known in computer science as the NAND and the NNOR operators.
+
For this reason, that is, by virtue of their precedence in the orders
+
of construction and derivation, these operations have to be regarded
+
as the simplest and the most primitive in principle, even if they are
+
scarcely recognized as lying among the more familiar elements of logic.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
I am throwing together a wide variety of different operations into each
+
of the bins labeled "additive" and "multiplicative", but it is easy to
+
observe a natural organization and even some relations approaching
+
isomorphisms among and between the members of each class.
+
+
The relation between logical disjunction and set-theoretic union and the
+
relation between logical conjunction and set-theoretic intersection ought
+
to be clear enough for the purposes of the immediately present context.
+
In any case, all of these relations are scheduled to receive a thorough
+
examination in a subsequent discussion (Subsection 1.3.10.13). But the
+
relation of a set-theoretic union to a category-theoretic co-product and
+
the relation of a set-theoretic intersection to a syntactic concatenation
+
deserve a closer look at this point.
+
+
The effect of a co-product as a "disjointed union", in other words, that
+
creates an object tantamount to a disjoint union of sets in the resulting
+
co-product even if some of these sets intersect non-trivially and even if
+
some of them are identical "in reality", can be achieved in several ways.
+
The most usual conception is that of making a "separate copy", for each
+
part of the intended co-product, of the set that is intended to go there.
+
Often one thinks of the set that is assigned to a particular part of the
+
co-product as being distinguished by a particular "color", in other words,
+
by the attachment of a distinct "index", "label", or "tag", being a marker
+
that is inherited by and passed on to every element of the set in that part.
+
A concrete image of this construction can be achieved by imagining that each
+
set and each element of each set is placed in an ordered pair with the sign
+
of its color, index, label, or tag. One describes this as the "injection"
+
of each set into the corresponding "part" of the co-product.
+
+
For example, given the sets P and Q, overlapping or not, one can define
+
the "indexed" sets or the "marked" sets P_[1] and Q_[2], amounting to the
+
copy of P into the first part of the co-product and the copy of Q into the
+
second part of the co-product, in the following manner:
+
+
P_[1] = <P, 1> = {<x, 1> : x in P},
+
+
Q_[2] = <Q, 2> = {<x, 2> : x in Q}.
+
+
Using the sign "]_[" for this construction, the "sum", the "co-product",
+
or the "disjointed union" of P and Q in that order can be represented as
+
the ordinary disjoint union of P_[1] and Q_[2].
+
+
P ]_[ Q = P_[1] |_| Q_[2].
+
+
The concatenation L_1 · L_2 of the formal languages L_1 and L_2 is
+
just the cartesian product of sets L_1 x L_2 without the extra x's,
+
but the relation of cartesian products to set-theoretic intersections
+
and thus to logical conjunctions is far from being clear. One way of
+
seeing a type of relation is to focus on the information that is needed
+
to specify each construction, and thus to reflect on the signs that are
+
used to carry this information. As a first approach to the topic of
+
information, according to a strategy that seeks to be as elementary
+
and as informal as possible, I introduce the following set of ideas,
+
intended to be taken in a very provisional way.
+
+
A "stricture" is a specification of a certain set in a certain place,
+
relative to a number of other sets, yet to be specified. It is assumed
+
that one knows enough to tell if two strictures are equivalent as pieces
+
of information, but any more determinate indications, like names for the
+
places that are mentioned in the stricture, or bounds on the number of
+
places that are involved, are regarded as being extraneous impositions,
+
outside the proper concern of the definition, no matter how convenient
+
they are found to be for a particular discussion. As a schematic form
+
of illustration, a stricture can be pictured in the following shape:
+
+
"... x X x Q x X x ..."
+
+
A "strait" is the object that is specified by a stricture, in effect,
+
a certain set in a certain place of an otherwise yet to be specified
+
relation. Somewhat sketchily, the strait that corresponds to the
+
stricture just given can be pictured in the following shape:
+
+
... x X x Q x X x ...
+
+
In this picture, Q is a certain set, and X is the universe of discourse
+
that is relevant to a given discussion. Since a stricture does not, by
+
itself, contain a sufficient amount of information to specify the number
+
of sets that it intends to set in place, or even to specify the absolute
+
location of the set that its does set in place, it appears to place an
+
unspecified number of unspecified sets in a vague and uncertain strait.
+
Taken out of its interpretive context, the residual information that a
+
stricture can convey makes all of the following potentially equivalent
+
as strictures:
+
+
"Q", "XxQxX", "XxXxQxXxX", ...
+
+
With respect to what these strictures specify, this
+
leaves all of the following equivalent as straits:
+
+
Q = XxQxX = XxXxQxXxX = ...
+
+
Within the framework of a particular discussion, it is customary to
+
set a bound on the number of places and to limit the variety of sets
+
that are regarded as being under active consideration, and it is also
+
convenient to index the places of the indicated relations, and of their
+
encompassing cartesian products, in some fixed way. But the whole idea
+
of a stricture is to specify a strait that is capable of extending through
+
and beyond any fixed frame of discussion. In other words, a stricture is
+
conceived to constrain a strait at a certain point, and then to leave it
+
literally embedded, if tacitly expressed, in a yet to be fully specified
+
relation, one that involves an unspecified number of unspecified domains.
+
+
A quantity of information is a measure of constraint. In this respect,
+
a set of comparable strictures is ordered on account of the information
+
that each one conveys, and a system of comparable straits is ordered in
+
accord with the amount of information that it takes to pin each one of
+
them down. Strictures that are more constraining and straits that are
+
more constrained are placed at higher levels of information than those
+
that are less so, and entities that involve more information are said
+
to have a greater "complexity" in comparison with those entities that
+
involve less information, that are said to have a greater "simplicity".
+
+
In order to create a concrete example, let me now institute a frame of
+
discussion where the number of places in a relation is bounded at two,
+
and where the variety of sets under active consideration is limited to
+
the typical subsets P and Q of a universe X. Under these conditions,
+
one can use the following sorts of expression as schematic strictures:
+
+
| "X" , "P" , "Q" ,
+
|
+
| "XxX", "XxP", "XxQ",
+
|
+
| "PxX", "PxP", "PxQ",
+
|
+
| "QxX", "QxP", "QxQ".
+
+
These strictures and their corresponding straits are stratified according
+
to their amounts of information, or their levels of constraint, as follows:
+
+
| High: "PxP", "PxQ", "QxP", "QxQ".
+
|
+
| Med: "P" , "XxP", "PxX".
+
|
+
| Med: "Q" , "XxQ", "QxX".
+
|
+
| Low: "X" , "XxX".
+
+
Within this framework, the more complex strait PxQ can be expressed
+
in terms of the simpler straits, PxX and XxQ. More specifically,
+
it lends itself to being analyzed as their intersection, in the
+
following way:
+
+
PxQ = PxX |^| XxQ.
+
+
>From here it is easy to see the relation of concatenation, by virtue of
+
these types of intersection, to the logical conjunction of propositions.
+
The cartesian product PxQ is described by a conjunction of propositions,
+
namely, "P_<1> and Q_<2>", subject to the following interpretation:
+
+
1. "P_<1>" asserts that there is an element from
+
the set P in the first place of the product.
+
+
2. "Q_<2>" asserts that there is an element from
+
the set Q in the second place of the product.
+
+
The integration of these two pieces of information can be taken
+
in that measure to specify a yet to be fully determined relation.
+
+
In a corresponding fashion at the level of the elements,
+
the ordered pair <p, q> is described by a conjunction
+
of propositions, namely, "p_<1> and q_<2>", subject
+
to the following interpretation:
+
+
1. "p_<1>" says that p is in the first place
+
of the product element under construction.
+
+
2. "q_<2>" says that q is in the second place
+
of the product element under construction.
+
+
Notice that, in construing the cartesian product of the sets P and Q or the
+
concatenation of the languages L_1 and L_2 in this way, one shifts the level
+
of the active construction from the tupling of the elements in P and Q or the
+
concatenation of the strings that are internal to the languages L_1 and L_2 to
+
the concatenation of the external signs that it takes to indicate these sets or
+
these languages, in other words, passing to a conjunction of indexed propositions,
+
"P_<1> and Q_<2>", or to a conjunction of assertions, "L_1_<1> and L_2_<2>", that
+
marks the sets or the languages in question for insertion in the indicated places
+
of a product set or a product language, respectively. In effect, the subscripting
+
by the indices "<1>" and "<2>" can be recognized as a special case of concatenation,
+
albeit through the posting of editorial remarks from an external "mark-up" language.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.10 The Cactus Language: Stylistics (cont.)
+
+
In order to systematize the relations that strictures and straits placed
+
at higher levels of complexity, constraint, information, and organization
+
have with those that are placed at the associated lower levels, I introduce
+
the following pair of definitions:
+
+
The j^th "excerpt" of a stricture of the form "S_1 x ... x S_k", regarded
+
within a frame of discussion where the number of places is limited to k,
+
is the stricture of the form "X x ... x S_j x ... x X". In the proper
+
context, this can be written more succinctly as the stricture "S_j_<j>",
+
an assertion that places the j^th set in the j^th place of the product.
+
+
The j^th "extract" of a strait of the form S_1 x ... x S_k, constrained
+
to a frame of discussion where the number of places is restricted to k,
+
is the strait of the form X x ... x S_j x ... x X. In the appropriate
+
context, this can be denoted more succinctly by the stricture "S_j_<j>",
+
an assertion that places the j^th set in the j^th place of the product.
+
+
In these terms, a stricture of the form "S_1 x ... x S_k"
+
can be expressed in terms of simpler strictures, to wit,
+
as a conjunction of its k excerpts:
+
+
"S_1 x ... x S_k" = "S_1_<1>" & ... & "S_k_<k>".
+
+
In a similar vein, a strait of the form S_1 x ... x S_k
+
can be expressed in terms of simpler straits, namely,
+
as an intersection of its k extracts:
+
+
S_1 x ... x S_k = S_1_<1> |^| ... |^| S_k_<k>.
+
+
There is a measure of ambiguity that remains in this formulation,
+
but it is the best that I can do in the present informal context.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.11 The Cactus Language: Mechanics
+
+
| We are only now beginning to see how this works. Clearly one of the
+
| mechanisms for picking a reality is the sociohistorical sense of what
+
| is important -- which research program, with all its particularity of
+
| knowledge, seems most fundamental, most productive, most penetrating.
+
| The very judgments which make us push narrowly forward simultaneously
+
| make us forget how little we know. And when we look back at history,
+
| where the lesson is plain to find, we often fail to imagine ourselves
+
| in a parallel situation. We ascribe the differences in world view
+
| to error, rather than to unexamined but consistent and internally
+
| justified choice.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein, "Idols", page 38.
+
|
+
| Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|"Idols of Modern Science & The Reconstruction of Knowledge", pages 37-68 in:
+
|
+
| Marcus G. Raskin & Herbert J. Bernstein,
+
|'New Ways of Knowing: The Sciences, Society, & Reconstructive Knowledge',
+
| Rowman & Littlefield, Totowa, NJ, 1987.
+
+
In this Subsection, I discuss the "mechanics" of parsing the
+
cactus language into the corresponding class of computational
+
data structures. This provides each sentence of the language
+
with a translation into a computational form that articulates
+
its syntactic structure and prepares it for automated modes of
+
processing and evaluation. For this purpose, it is necessary
+
to describe the target data structures at a fairly high level
+
of abstraction only, ignoring the details of address pointers
+
and record structures and leaving the more operational aspects
+
of implementation to the imagination of prospective programmers.
+
In this way, I can put off to another stage of elaboration and
+
refinement the description of the program that constructs these
+
pointers and operates on these graph-theoretic data structures.
+
+
The structure of a "painted cactus", insofar as it presents itself
+
to the visual imagination, can be described as follows. The overall
+
structure, as given by its underlying graph, falls within the species
+
of graph that is commonly known as a "rooted cactus", and the only novel
+
feature that it adds to this is that each of its nodes can be "painted"
+
with a finite sequence of "paints", chosen from a "palette" that is given
+
by the parametric set {" "} |_| !P! = {m_1} |_| {p_1, ..., p_k}.
+
+
It is conceivable, from a purely graph-theoretical point of view, to have
+
a class of cacti that are painted but not rooted, and so it is frequently
+
necessary, for the sake of precision, to more exactly pinpoint the target
+
species of graphical structure as a "painted and rooted cactus" (PARC).
+
+
A painted cactus, as a rooted graph, has a distinguished "node" that is
+
called its "root". By starting from the root and working recursively,
+
the rest of its structure can be described in the following fashion.
+
+
Each "node" of a PARC consists of a graphical "point" or "vertex" plus
+
a finite sequence of "attachments", described in relative terms as the
+
attachments "at" or "to" that node. An empty sequence of attachments
+
defines the "empty node". Otherwise, each attachment is one of three
+
kinds: a blank, a paint, or a type of PARC that is called a "lobe".
+
+
Each "lobe" of a PARC consists of a directed graphical "cycle" plus a
+
finite sequence of "accoutrements", described in relative terms as the
+
accoutrements "of" or "on" that lobe. Recalling the circumstance that
+
every lobe that comes under consideration comes already attached to a
+
particular node, exactly one vertex of the corresponding cycle is the
+
vertex that comes from that very node. The remaining vertices of the
+
cycle have their definitions filled out according to the accoutrements
+
of the lobe in question. An empty sequence of accoutrements is taken
+
to be tantamount to a sequence that contains a single empty node as its
+
unique accoutrement, and either one of these ways of approaching it can
+
be regarded as defining a graphical structure that is called a "needle"
+
or a "terminal edge". Otherwise, each accoutrement of a lobe is itself
+
an arbitrary PARC.
+
+
Although this definition of a lobe in terms of its intrinsic structural
+
components is logically sufficient, it is also useful to characterize the
+
structure of a lobe in comparative terms, that is, to view the structure
+
that typifies a lobe in relation to the structures of other PARC's and to
+
mark the inclusion of this special type within the general run of PARC's.
+
This approach to the question of types results in a form of description
+
that appears to be a bit more analytic, at least, in mnemonic or prima
+
facie terms, if not ultimately more revealing. Working in this vein,
+
a "lobe" can be characterized as a special type of PARC that is called
+
an "unpainted root plant" (UR-plant).
+
+
An "UR-plant" is a PARC of a simpler sort, at least, with respect to the
+
recursive ordering of structures that is being followed here. As a type,
+
it is defined by the presence of two properties, that of being "planted"
+
and that of having an "unpainted root". These are defined as follows:
+
+
1. A PARC is "planted" if its list of attachments has just one PARC.
+
+
2. A PARC is "UR" if its list of attachments has no blanks or paints.
+
+
In short, an UR-planted PARC has a single PARC as its only attachment,
+
and since this attachment is prevented from being a blank or a paint,
+
the single attachment at its root has to be another sort of structure,
+
that which we call a "lobe".
+
+
To express the description of a PARC in terms of its nodes, each node
+
can be specified in the fashion of a functional expression, letting a
+
citation of the generic function name "Node" be followed by a list of
+
arguments that enumerates the attachments of the node in question, and
+
letting a citation of the generic function name "Lobe" be followed by a
+
list of arguments that details the accoutrements of the lobe in question.
+
Thus, one can write expressions of the following forms:
+
+
1. Node^0 = Node()
+
+
= a node with no attachments.
+
+
Node^k_j C_j = Node(C_1, ..., C_k)
+
+
= a node with the attachments C_1, ..., C_k.
+
+
2. Lobe^0 = Lobe()
+
+
= a lobe with no accoutrements.
+
+
Lobe^k_j C_j = Lobe(C_1, ..., C_k)
+
+
= a lobe with the accoutrements C_1, ..., C_k.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.11 The Cactus Language: Mechanics (cont.)
+
+
Working from a structural description of the cactus language,
+
or any suitable formal grammar for !C!(!P!), it is possible to
+
give a recursive definition of the function called "Parse" that
+
maps each sentence in PARCE(!P!) to the corresponding graph in
+
PARC(!P!). One way to do this proceeds as follows:
+
+
1. The parse of the concatenation Conc^k of the k sentences S_j,
+
for j = 1 to k, is defined recursively as follows:
+
+
a. Parse(Conc^0) = Node^0.
+
+
b. For k > 0,
+
+
Parse(Conc^k_j S_j) = Node^k_j Parse(S_j).
+
+
2. The parse of the surcatenation Surc^k of the k sentences S_j,
+
for j = 1 to k, is defined recursively as follows:
+
+
a. Parse(Surc^0) = Lobe^0.
+
+
b. For k > 0,
+
+
Parse(Surc^k_j S_j) = Lobe^k_j Parse(S_j).
+
+
For ease of reference, Table 12 summarizes the mechanics of these parsing rules.
+
+
Table 12. Algorithmic Translation Rules
+
o------------------------o---------o------------------------o
+
| | Parse | |
+
| Sentence in PARCE | --> | Graph in PARC |
+
o------------------------o---------o------------------------o
+
| | | |
+
| Conc^0 | --> | Node^0 |
+
| | | |
+
| Conc^k_j S_j | --> | Node^k_j Parse(S_j) |
+
| | | |
+
| Surc^0 | --> | Lobe^0 |
+
| | | |
+
| Surc^k_j S_j | --> | Lobe^k_j Parse(S_j) |
+
| | | |
+
o------------------------o---------o------------------------o
+
+
A "substructure" of a PARC is defined recursively as follows. Starting
+
at the root node of the cactus C, any attachment is a substructure of C.
+
If a substructure is a blank or a paint, then it constitutes a minimal
+
substructure, meaning that no further substructures of C arise from it.
+
If a substructure is a lobe, then each one of its accoutrements is also
+
a substructure of C, and has to be examined for further substructures.
+
+
The concept of substructure can be used to define varieties of deletion
+
and erasure operations that respect the structure of the abstract graph.
+
For the purposes of this depiction, a blank symbol " " is treated as
+
a "primer", in other words, as a "clear paint", a "neutral tint", or
+
a "white wash". In effect, one is letting m_1 = p_0. In this frame
+
of discussion, it is useful to make the following distinction:
+
+
1. To "delete" a substructure is to replace it with an empty node,
+
in effect, to reduce the whole structure to a trivial point.
+
+
2. To "erase" a substructure is to replace it with a blank symbol,
+
in effect, to paint it out of the picture or to overwrite it.
+
+
A "bare" PARC, loosely referred to as a "bare cactus", is a PARC on the
+
empty palette !P! = {}. In other veins, a bare cactus can be described
+
in several different ways, depending on how the form arises in practice.
+
+
1. Leaning on the definition of a bare PARCE, a bare PARC can be
+
described as the kind of a parse graph that results from parsing
+
a bare cactus expression, in other words, as the kind of a graph
+
that issues from the requirements of processing a sentence of
+
the bare cactus language !C!^0 = PARCE^0.
+
+
2. To express it more in its own terms, a bare PARC can be defined
+
by tracing the recursive definition of a generic PARC, but then
+
by detaching an independent form of description from the source
+
of that analogy. The method is sufficiently sketched as follows:
+
+
a. A "bare PARC" is a PARC whose attachments
+
are limited to blanks and "bare lobes".
+
+
b. A "bare lobe" is a lobe whose accoutrements
+
are limited to bare PARC's.
+
+
3. In practice, a bare cactus is usually encountered in the process
+
of analyzing or handling an arbitrary PARC, the circumstances of
+
which frequently call for deleting or erasing all of its paints.
+
In particular, this generally makes it easier to observe the
+
various properties of its underlying graphical structure.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.12 The Cactus Language: Semantics
+
+
| Alas, and yet what 'are' you, my written and painted thoughts!
+
| It is not long ago that you were still so many-coloured,
+
| young and malicious, so full of thorns and hidden
+
| spices you made me sneeze and laugh -- and now?
+
| You have already taken off your novelty and
+
| some of you, I fear, are on the point of
+
| becoming truths: they already look so
+
| immortal, so pathetically righteous,
+
| so boring!
+
|
+
| Friedrich Nietzsche, 'Beyond Good and Evil', Paragraph 296.
+
|
+
| Friedrich Nietzsche,
+
|'Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future',
+
| trans. by R.J. Hollingdale, intro. by Michael Tanner,
+
| Penguin Books, London, UK, 1973, 1990.
+
+
In this Subsection, I describe a particular semantics for the
+
painted cactus language, telling what meanings I aim to attach
+
to its bare syntactic forms. This supplies an "interpretation"
+
for this parametric family of formal languages, but it is good
+
to remember that it forms just one of many such interpretations
+
that are conceivable and even viable. In deed, the distinction
+
between the object domain and the sign domain can be observed in
+
the fact that many languages can be deployed to depict the same
+
set of objects and that any language worth its salt is bound to
+
to give rise to many different forms of interpretive saliency.
+
+
In formal settings, it is common to speak of "interpretation" as if it
+
created a direct connection between the signs of a formal language and
+
the objects of the intended domain, in other words, as if it determined
+
the denotative component of a sign relation. But a closer attention to
+
what goes on reveals that the process of interpretation is more indirect,
+
that what it does is to provide each sign of a prospectively meaningful
+
source language with a translation into an already established target
+
language, where "already established" means that its relationship to
+
pragmatic objects is taken for granted at the moment in question.
+
+
With this in mind, it is clear that interpretation is an affair of signs
+
that at best respects the objects of all of the signs that enter into it,
+
and so it is the connotative aspect of semiotics that is at stake here.
+
There is nothing wrong with my saying that I interpret a sentence of a
+
formal language as a sign that refers to a function or to a proposition,
+
so long as you understand that this reference is likely to be achieved
+
by way of more familiar and perhaps less formal signs that you already
+
take to denote those objects.
+
+
On entering a context where a logical interpretation is intended for the
+
sentences of a formal language there are a few conventions that make it
+
easier to make the translation from abstract syntactic forms to their
+
intended semantic senses. Although these conventions are expressed in
+
unnecessarily colorful terms, from a purely abstract point of view, they
+
do provide a useful array of connotations that help to negotiate what is
+
otherwise a difficult transition. This terminology is introduced as the
+
need for it arises in the process of interpreting the cactus language.
+
+
The task of this Subsection is to specify a "semantic function" for
+
the sentences of the cactus language !L! = !C!(!P!), in other words,
+
to define a mapping that "interprets" each sentence of !C!(!P!) as
+
a sentence that says something, as a sentence that bears a meaning,
+
in short, as a sentence that denotes a proposition, and thus as a
+
sign of an indicator function. When the syntactic sentences of a
+
formal language are given a referent significance in logical terms,
+
for example, as denoting propositions or indicator functions, then
+
each form of syntactic combination takes on a corresponding form
+
of logical significance.
+
+
By way of providing a logical interpretation for the cactus language,
+
I introduce a family of operators on indicator functions that are
+
called "propositional connectives", and I distinguish these from
+
the associated family of syntactic combinations that are called
+
"sentential connectives", where the relationship between these
+
two realms of connection is exactly that between objects and
+
their signs. A propositional connective, as an entity of a
+
well-defined functional and operational type, can be treated
+
in every way as a logical or a mathematical object, and thus
+
as the type of object that can be denoted by the corresponding
+
form of syntactic entity, namely, the sentential connective that
+
is appropriate to the case in question.
+
+
There are two basic types of connectives, called the "blank connectives"
+
and the "bound connectives", respectively, with one connective of each
+
type for each natural number k = 0, 1, 2, 3, ... .
+
+
1. The "blank connective" of k places is signified by the
+
concatenation of the k sentences that fill those places.
+
+
For the special case of k = 0, the "blank connective" is taken to
+
be an empty string or a blank symbol -- it does not matter which,
+
since both are assigned the same denotation among propositions.
+
For the generic case of k > 0, the "blank connective" takes
+
the form "S_1 · ... · S_k". In the type of data that is
+
called a "text", the raised dots "·" are usually omitted,
+
supplanted by whatever number of spaces and line breaks
+
serve to improve the readability of the resulting text.
+
+
2. The "bound connective" of k places is signified by the
+
surcatenation of the k sentences that fill those places.
+
+
For the special case of k = 0, the "bound connective" is taken to
+
be an expression of the form "-()-", "-( )-", "-( )-", and so on,
+
with any number of blank symbols between the parentheses, all of
+
which are assigned the same logical denotation among propositions.
+
For the generic case of k > 0, the "bound connective" takes the
+
form "-(S_1, ..., S_k)-".
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.12 The Cactus Language: Semantics (cont.)
+
+
At this point, there are actually two different "dialects", "scripts",
+
or "modes" of presentation for the cactus language that need to be
+
interpreted, in other words, that need to have a semantic function
+
defined on their domains.
+
+
a. There is the literal formal language of strings in PARCE(!P!),
+
the "painted and rooted cactus expressions" that constitute
+
the langauge !L! = !C!(!P!) c !A!* = (!M! |_| !P!)*.
+
+
b. There is the figurative formal language of graphs in PARC(!P!),
+
the "painted and rooted cacti" themselves, a parametric family
+
of graphs or a species of computational data structures that
+
is graphically analogous to the language of literal strings.
+
+
Of course, these two modalities of formal language, like written and
+
spoken natural languages, are meant to have compatible interpretations,
+
and so it is usually sufficient to give just the meanings of either one.
+
All that remains is to provide a "codomain" or a "target space" for the
+
intended semantic function, in other words, to supply a suitable range
+
of logical meanings for the memberships of these languages to map into.
+
Out of the many interpretations that are formally possible to arrange,
+
one way of doing this proceeds by making the following definitions:
+
+
1. The "conjunction" Conj^J_j Q_j of a set of propositions, {Q_j : j in J},
+
is a proposition that is true if and only if each one of the Q_j is true.
+
+
Conj^J_j Q_j is true <=> Q_j is true for every j in J.
+
+
2. The "surjunction" Surj^J_j Q_j of a set of propositions, {Q_j : j in J},
+
is a proposition that is true if and only if just one of the Q_j is untrue.
+
+
Surj^J_j Q_j is true <=> Q_j is untrue for unique j in J.
+
+
If the number of propositions that are being joined together is finite,
+
then the conjunction and the surjunction can be represented by means of
+
sentential connectives, incorporating the sentences that represent these
+
propositions into finite strings of symbols.
+
+
If J is finite, for instance, if J constitutes the interval j = 1 to k,
+
and if each proposition Q_j is represented by a sentence S_j, then the
+
following strategies of expression are open:
+
+
1. The conjunction Conj^J_j Q_j can be represented by a sentence that
+
is constructed by concatenating the S_j in the following fashion:
+
+
Conj^J_j Q_j <-< S_1 S_2 ... S_k.
+
+
2. The surjunction Surj^J_j Q_j can be represented by a sentence that
+
is constructed by surcatenating the S_j in the following fashion:
+
+
Surj^J_j Q_j <-< -(S_1, S_2, ..., S_k)-.
+
+
If one opts for a mode of interpretation that moves more directly from
+
the parse graph of a sentence to the potential logical meaning of both
+
the PARC and the PARCE, then the following specifications are in order:
+
+
A cactus rooted at a particular node is taken to represent what that
+
node denotes, its logical denotation or its logical interpretation.
+
+
1. The logical denotation of a node is the logical conjunction of that node's
+
"arguments", which are defined as the logical denotations of that node's
+
attachments. The logical denotation of either a blank symbol or an empty
+
node is the boolean value %1% = "true". The logical denotation of the
+
paint p_j is the proposition P_j, a proposition that is regarded as
+
"primitive", at least, with respect to the level of analysis that
+
is represented in the current instance of !C!(!P!).
+
+
2. The logical denotation of a lobe is the logical surjunction of that lobe's
+
"arguments", which are defined as the logical denotations of that lobe's
+
accoutrements. As a corollary, the logical denotation of the parse graph
+
of "-()-", otherwise called a "needle", is the boolean value %0% = "false".
+
+
If one takes the point of view that PARC's and PARCE's amount to a
+
pair of intertranslatable languages for the same domain of objects,
+
then the "spiny bracket" notation, as in "-[C_j]-" or "-[S_j]-",
+
can be used on either domain of signs to indicate the logical
+
denotation of a cactus C_j or the logical denotation of
+
a sentence S_j, respectively.
+
+
Tables 13.1 and 13.2 summarize the relations that serve to connect the
+
formal language of sentences with the logical language of propositions.
+
Between these two realms of expression there is a family of graphical
+
data structures that arise in parsing the sentences and that serve to
+
facilitate the performance of computations on the indicator functions.
+
The graphical language supplies an intermediate form of representation
+
between the formal sentences and the indicator functions, and the form
+
of mediation that it provides is very useful in rendering the possible
+
connections between the other two languages conceivable in fact, not to
+
mention in carrying out the necessary translations on a practical basis.
+
These Tables include this intermediate domain in their Central Columns.
+
Between their First and Middle Columns they illustrate the mechanics of
+
parsing the abstract sentences of the cactus language into the graphical
+
data structures of the corresponding species. Between their Middle and
+
Final Columns they summarize the semantics of interpreting the graphical
+
forms of representation for the purposes of reasoning with propositions.
+
+
Table 13.1 Semantic Translations: Functional Form
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | Par | | Den | |
+
| Sentence | --> | Graph | --> | Proposition |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| S_j | --> | C_j | --> | Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| Conc^0 | --> | Node^0 | --> | %1% |
+
| | | | | |
+
| Conc^k_j S_j | --> | Node^k_j C_j | --> | Conj^k_j Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| Surc^0 | --> | Lobe^0 | --> | %0% |
+
| | | | | |
+
| Surc^k_j S_j | --> | Lobe^k_j C_j | --> | Surj^k_j Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
+
Table 13.2 Semantic Translations: Equational Form
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | Par | | Den | |
+
| -[Sentence]- | = | -[Graph]- | = | Proposition |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| -[S_j]- | = | -[C_j]- | = | Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| -[Conc^0]- | = | -[Node^0]- | = | %1% |
+
| | | | | |
+
| -[Conc^k_j S_j]- | = | -[Node^k_j C_j]- | = | Conj^k_j Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| -[Surc^0]- | = | -[Lobe^0]- | = | %0% |
+
| | | | | |
+
| -[Surc^k_j S_j]- | = | -[Lobe^k_j C_j]- | = | Surj^k_j Q_j |
+
| | | | | |
+
o-------------------o-----o-------------------o-----o-------------------o
+
+
Aside from their common topic, the two Tables present slightly different
+
ways of conceptualizing the operations that go to establish their maps.
+
Table 13.1 records the functional associations that connect each domain
+
with the next, taking the triplings of a sentence S_j, a cactus C_j, and
+
a proposition Q_j as basic data, and fixing the rest by recursion on these.
+
Table 13.2 records these associations in the form of equations, treating
+
sentences and graphs as alternative kinds of signs, and generalizing the
+
spiny bracket operator to indicate the proposition that either denotes.
+
It should be clear at this point that either scheme of translation puts
+
the sentences, the graphs, and the propositions that it associates with
+
each other roughly in the roles of the signs, the interpretants, and the
+
objects, respectively, whose triples define an appropriate sign relation.
+
Indeed, the "roughly" can be made "exactly" as soon as the domains of
+
a suitable sign relation are specified precisely.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.12 The Cactus Language: Semantics (cont.)
+
+
A good way to illustrate the action of the conjunction and surjunction
+
operators is to demonstate how they can be used to construct all of the
+
boolean functions on k variables, just now, let us say, for k = 0, 1, 2.
+
+
A boolean function on 0 variables is just a boolean constant F^0 in the
+
boolean domain %B% = {%0%, %1%}. Table 14 shows several different ways
+
of referring to these elements, just for the sake of consistency using
+
the same format that will be used in subsequent Tables, no matter how
+
degenerate it tends to appears in the immediate case:
+
+
Column 1 lists each boolean element or boolean function under its
+
ordinary constant name or under a succinct nickname, respectively.
+
+
Column 2 lists each boolean function in a style of function name "F^i_j"
+
that is constructed as follows: The superscript "i" gives the dimension
+
of the functional domain, that is, the number of its functional variables,
+
and the subscript "j" is a binary string that recapitulates the functional
+
values, using the obvious translation of boolean values into binary values.
+
+
Column 3 lists the functional values for each boolean function, or possibly
+
a boolean element appearing in the guise of a function, for each combination
+
of its domain values.
+
+
Column 4 shows the usual expressions of these elements in the cactus language,
+
conforming to the practice of omitting the strike-throughs in display formats.
+
Here I illustrate also the useful convention of sending the expression "(())"
+
as a visible stand-in for the expression of a constantly "true" truth value,
+
one that would otherwise be represented by a blank expression, and tend to
+
elude our giving it much notice in the context of more demonstrative texts.
+
+
Table 14. Boolean Functions on Zero Variables
+
o----------o----------o-------------------------------------------o----------o
+
| Constant | Function | F() | Function |
+
o----------o----------o-------------------------------------------o----------o
+
| | | | |
+
| %0% | F^0_0 | %0% | () |
+
| | | | |
+
| %1% | F^0_1 | %1% | (()) |
+
| | | | |
+
o----------o----------o-------------------------------------------o----------o
+
+
Table 15 presents the boolean functions on one variable, F^1 : %B% -> %B%,
+
of which there are precisely four. Here, Column 1 codes the contents of
+
Column 2 in a more concise form, compressing the lists of boolean values,
+
recorded as bits in the subscript string, into their decimal equivalents.
+
Naturally, the boolean constants reprise themselves in this new setting
+
as constant functions on one variable. Thus, one has the synonymous
+
expressions for constant functions that are expressed in the next
+
two chains of equations:
+
+
| F^1_0 = F^1_00 = %0% : %B% -> %B%
+
|
+
| F^1_3 = F^1_11 = %1% : %B% -> %B%
+
+
As for the rest, the other two functions are easily recognized as corresponding
+
to the one-place logical connectives, or the monadic operators on %B%. Thus,
+
the function F^1_1 = F^1_01 is recognizable as the negation operation, and
+
the function F^1_2 = F^1_10 is obviously the identity operation.
+
+
Table 15. Boolean Functions on One Variable
+
o----------o----------o-------------------------------------------o----------o
+
| Function | Function | F(x) | Function |
+
o----------o----------o---------------------o---------------------o----------o
+
| | | F(%0%) | F(%1%) | |
+
o----------o----------o---------------------o---------------------o----------o
+
| | | | | |
+
| F^1_0 | F^1_00 | %0% | %0% | ( ) |
+
| | | | | |
+
| F^1_1 | F^1_01 | %0% | %1% | (x) |
+
| | | | | |
+
| F^1_2 | F^1_10 | %1% | %0% | x |
+
| | | | | |
+
| F^1_3 | F^1_11 | %1% | %1% | (( )) |
+
| | | | | |
+
o----------o----------o---------------------o---------------------o----------o
+
+
Table 16 presents the boolean functions on two variables, F^2 : %B%^2 -> %B%,
+
of which there are precisely sixteen in number. As before, all of the boolean
+
functions of fewer variables are subsumed in this Table, though under a set of
+
alternative names and possibly different interpretations. Just to acknowledge
+
a few of the more notable pseudonyms:
+
+
The constant function %0% : %B%^2 -> %B% appears under the name of F^2_00.
+
+
The constant function %1% : %B%^2 -> %B% appears under the name of F^2_15.
+
+
The negation and identity of the first variable are F^2_03 and F^2_12, resp.
+
+
The negation and identity of the other variable are F^2_05 and F^2_10, resp.
+
+
The logical conjunction is given by the function F^2_08 (x, y) = x · y.
+
+
The logical disjunction is given by the function F^2_14 (x, y) = ((x)(y)).
+
+
Functions expressing the "conditionals", "implications",
+
or "if-then" statements are given in the following ways:
+
+
[x => y] = F^2_11 (x, y) = (x (y)) = [not x without y].
+
+
[x <= y] = F^2_13 (x, y) = ((x) y) = [not y without x].
+
+
The function that corresponds to the "biconditional",
+
the "equivalence", or the "if and only" statement is
+
exhibited in the following fashion:
+
+
[x <=> y] = [x = y] = F^2_09 (x, y) = ((x , y)).
+
+
Finally, there is a boolean function that is logically associated with
+
the "exclusive disjunction", "inequivalence", or "not equals" statement,
+
algebraically associated with the "binary sum" or "bitsum" operation,
+
and geometrically associated with the "symmetric difference" of sets.
+
This function is given by:
+
+
[x =/= y] = [x + y] = F^2_06 (x, y) = (x , y).
+
+
Table 16. Boolean Functions on Two Variables
+
o----------o----------o-------------------------------------------o----------o
+
| Function | Function | F(x, y) | Function |
+
o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o
+
| | | %1%, %1% | %1%, %0% | %0%, %1% | %0%, %0% | |
+
o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_00 | F^2_0000 | %0% | %0% | %0% | %0% | () |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_01 | F^2_0001 | %0% | %0% | %0% | %1% | (x)(y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_02 | F^2_0010 | %0% | %0% | %1% | %0% | (x) y |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_03 | F^2_0011 | %0% | %0% | %1% | %1% | (x) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_04 | F^2_0100 | %0% | %1% | %0% | %0% | x (y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_05 | F^2_0101 | %0% | %1% | %0% | %1% | (y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_06 | F^2_0110 | %0% | %1% | %1% | %0% | (x, y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_07 | F^2_0111 | %0% | %1% | %1% | %1% | (x y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_08 | F^2_1000 | %1% | %0% | %0% | %0% | x y |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_09 | F^2_1001 | %1% | %0% | %0% | %1% | ((x, y)) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_10 | F^2_1010 | %1% | %0% | %1% | %0% | y |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_11 | F^2_1011 | %1% | %0% | %1% | %1% | (x (y)) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_12 | F^2_1100 | %1% | %1% | %0% | %0% | x |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_13 | F^2_1101 | %1% | %1% | %0% | %1% | ((x) y) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_14 | F^2_1110 | %1% | %1% | %1% | %0% | ((x)(y)) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
| F^2_15 | F^2_1111 | %1% | %1% | %1% | %1% | (()) |
+
| | | | | | | |
+
o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o
+
+
Let me now address one last question that may have occurred to some.
+
What has happened, in this suggested scheme of functional reasoning,
+
to the distinction that is quite pointedly made by careful logicians
+
between (1) the connectives called "conditionals" and symbolized by
+
the signs "->" and "<-", and (2) the assertions called "implications"
+
and symbolized by the signs "=>" and "<=", and, in a related question:
+
What has happened to the distinction that is equally insistently made
+
between (3) the connective called the "biconditional" and signified by
+
the sign "<->" and (4) the assertion that is called an "equivalence"
+
and signified by the sign "<=>"? My answer is this: For my part,
+
I am deliberately avoiding making these distinctions at the level
+
of syntax, preferring to treat them instead as distinctions in
+
the use of boolean functions, turning on whether the function
+
is mentioned directly and used to compute values on arguments,
+
or whether its inverse is being invoked to indicate the fibers
+
of truth or untruth under the propositional function in question.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
In this Subsection, I finally bring together many of what may
+
have appeared to be wholly independent threads of development,
+
in the hope of paying off a percentage of my promissory notes,
+
even if a goodly number my creditors have no doubt long since
+
forgotten, if not exactly forgiven the debentures in question.
+
+
For ease of reference, I repeat here a couple of the
+
definitions that are needed again in this discussion.
+
+
| A "boolean connection" of degree k, also known as a "boolean function"
+
| on k variables, is a map of the form F : %B%^k -> %B%. In other words,
+
| a boolean connection of degree k is a proposition about things in the
+
| universe of discourse X = %B%^k.
+
|
+
| An "imagination" of degree k on X is a k-tuple of propositions
+
| about things in the universe X. By way of displaying the kinds
+
| of notation that are used to express this idea, the imagination
+
| #f# = <f_1, ..., f_k> is can be given as a sequence of indicator
+
| functions f_j : X -> %B%, for j = 1 to k. All of these features
+
| of the typical imagination #f# can be summed up in either one of
+
| two ways: either in the form of a membership statement, stating
+
| words to the effect that #f# belongs to the space (X -> %B%)^k,
+
| or in the form of the type declaration that #f# : (X -> %B%)^k,
+
| though perhaps the latter specification is slightly more precise
+
| than the former.
+
+
The definition of the "stretch" operation and the uses of the
+
various brands of denotational operators can be reviewed here:
+
+
055. http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg07466.html
+
057. http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg07469.html
+
+
070. http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg03473.html
+
071. http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg03479.html
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
+
1.3.10.13 Stretching Exercises
+
+
Taking up the preceding arrays of particular connections, namely,
+
the boolean functions on two or less variables, it possible to
+
illustrate the use of the stretch operation in a variety of
+
concrete cases.
+
+
For example, suppose that F is a connection of the form F : %B%^2 -> %B%,
+
that is, any one of the sixteen possibilities in Table 16, while p and q
+
are propositions of the form p, q : X -> %B%, that is, propositions about
+
things in the universe X, or else the indicators of sets contained in X.
+
+
Then one has the imagination #f# = <f_1, f_2> = <p, q> : (X -> %B%)^2,
+
and the stretch of the connection F to #f# on X amounts to a proposition
+
F^$ <p, q> : X -> %B%, usually written as "F^$ (p, q)" and vocalized as
+
the "stretch of F to p and q". If one is concerned with many different
+
propositions about things in X, or if one is abstractly indifferent to
+
the particular choices for p and q, then one can detach the operator
+
F^$ : (X -> %B%)^2 -> (X -> %B%), called the "stretch of F over X",
+
and consider it in isolation from any concrete application.
+
+
When the "cactus notation" is used to represent boolean functions,
+
a single "$" sign at the end of the expression is enough to remind
+
a reader that the connections are meant to be stretched to several
+
propositions on a universe X.
+
+
For instance, take the connection F : %B%^2 -> %B% such that:
+
+
F(x, y) = F^2_06 (x, y) = -(x, y)-.
+
+
This connection is the boolean function on a couple of variables x, y
+
that yields a value of %1% if and only if just one of x, y is not %1%,
+
that is, if and only if just one of x, y is %1%. There is clearly an
+
isomorphism between this connection, viewed as an operation on the
+
boolean domain %B% = {%0%, %1%}, and the dyadic operation on binary
+
values x, y in !B! = GF(2) that is otherwise known as "x + y".
+
+
The same connection F : %B%^2 -> %B% can also be read as a proposition
+
about things in the universe X = %B%^2. If S is a sentence that denotes
+
the proposition F, then the corresponding assertion says exactly what one
+
otherwise states by uttering "x is not equal to y". In such a case, one
+
has -[S]- = F, and all of the following expressions are ordinarily taken
+
as equivalent descriptions of the same set:
+
+
[| -[S]- |] = [| F |]
+
+
= F^(-1)(%1%)
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : S}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : F(x, y) = %1%}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : F(x, y)}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : -(x, y)- = %1%}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : -(x, y)- }
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : x exclusive-or y}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : just one true of x, y}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : x not equal to y}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : x <=/=> y}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : x =/= y}
+
+
= {<x, y> in %B%^2 : x + y}.
+
+
Notice the slight distinction, that I continue to maintain at this point,
+
between the logical values {false, true} and the algebraic values {0, 1}.
+
This makes it legitimate to write a sentence directly into the right side
+
of the set-builder expression, for instance, weaving the sentence S or the
+
sentence "x is not equal to y" into the context "{<x, y> in %B%^2 : ... }",
+
thereby obtaining the corresponding expressions listed above, while the
+
proposition F(x, y) can also be asserted more directly without equating
+
it to %1%, since it already has a value in {false, true}, and thus can
+
be taken as tantamount to an actual sentence.
+
+
If the appropriate safeguards can be kept in mind, avoiding all danger of
+
confusing propositions with sentences and sentences with assertions, then
+
the marks of these distinctions need not be forced to clutter the account
+
of the more substantive indications, that is, the ones that really matter.
+
If this level of understanding can be achieved, then it may be possible
+
to relax these restrictions, along with the absolute dichotomy between
+
algebraic and logical values, which tends to inhibit the flexibility
+
of interpretation.
+
+
This covers the properties of the connection F(x, y) = -(x, y)-,
+
treated as a proposition about things in the universe X = %B%^2.
+
Staying with this same connection, it is time to demonstrate how
+
it can be "stretched" into an operator on arbitrary propositions.
+
+
To continue the exercise, let p and q be arbitrary propositions about
+
things in the universe X, that is, maps of the form p, q : X -> %B%,
+
and suppose that p, q are indicator functions of the sets P, Q c X,
+
respectively. In other words, one has the following set of data:
+
+
| p = -{P}- : X -> %B%
+
|
+
| q = -{Q}- : X -> %B%
+
|
+
| <p, q> = < -{P}- , -{Q}- > : (X -> %B%)^2
+
+
Then one has an operator F^$, the stretch of the connection F over X,
+
and a proposition F^$ (p, q), the stretch of F to <p, q> on X, with
+
the following properties:
+
+
| F^$ = -( , )-^$ : (X -> %B%)^2 -> (X -> %B%)
+
|
+
| F^$ (p, q) = -(p, q)-^$ : X -> %B%
+
+
As a result, the application of the proposition F^$ (p, q) to each x in X
+
yields a logical value in %B%, all in accord with the following equations:
+
+
| F^$ (p, q)(x) = -(p, q)-^$ (x) in %B%
+
|
+
| ^ ^
+
| | |
+
| = =
+
| | |
+
| v v
+
|
+
| F(p(x), q(x)) = -(p(x), q(x))- in %B%
+
+
For each choice of propositions p and q about things in X, the stretch of
+
F to p and q on X is just another proposition about things in X, a simple
+
proposition in its own right, no matter how complex its current expression
+
or its present construction as F^$ (p, q) = -(p, q)^$ makes it appear in
+
relation to p and q. Like any other proposition about things in X, it
+
indicates a subset of X, namely, the fiber that is variously described
+
in the following ways:
+
+
[| F^$ (p, q) |] = [| -(p, q)-^$ |]
+
+
= (F^$ (p, q))^(-1)(%1%)
+
+
= {x in X : F^$ (p, q)(x)}
+
+
= {x in X : -(p, q)-^$ (x)}
+
+
= {x in X : -(p(x), q(x))- }
+
+
= {x in X : p(x) ± q(x)}
+
+
= {x in X : p(x) =/= q(x)}
+
+
= {x in X : -{P}- (x) =/= -{Q}- (x)}
+
+
= {x in X : x in P <=/=> x in Q}
+
+
= {x in X : x in P-Q or x in Q-P}
+
+
= {x in X : x in P-Q |_| Q-P}
+
+
= {x in X : x in P ± Q}
+
+
= P ± Q c X
+
+
= [|p|] ± [|q|] c X.
+
+
Which was to be shown.
+
+
o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o~~~~~~~~~o
+
</pre>