Changes

→‎Syntactic Transformations: mathematical markup
Line 2,799: Line 2,799:  
Going back to Rule 1, we see that it lists a pair of concrete sentences and authorizes exchanges in either direction between the syntactic structures that have these two forms.  But a sentence is any sign that denotes a proposition, and so there are any number of less obvious sentences that can be added to this list, extending the number of items that are licensed to be exchanged.  For example, a larger collection of equivalent sentences is recorded in Rule 4.
 
Going back to Rule 1, we see that it lists a pair of concrete sentences and authorizes exchanges in either direction between the syntactic structures that have these two forms.  But a sentence is any sign that denotes a proposition, and so there are any number of less obvious sentences that can be added to this list, extending the number of items that are licensed to be exchanged.  For example, a larger collection of equivalent sentences is recorded in Rule 4.
   −
<pre>
+
<br>
Rule 4
     −
If X c U is fixed
+
{| align="center" cellpadding="2" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black" width="90%"
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| width="2%"  | &nbsp;
 +
| width="18%" | &nbsp;
 +
| width="60%" | &nbsp;
 +
| align="center" width="20%" | <math>\text{Rule 4}\!</math>
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | &nbsp;
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | <math>\text{If}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | <math>Q \subseteq X ~\text{is fixed}</math>
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{and}\!</math>
 +
| <math>x \in X ~\text{is varied}</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{then}\!</math>
 +
| <math>\text{the following are equivalent:}\!</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | &nbsp;
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | <math>\text{R4a.}\!</math>
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | <math>x \in Q</math>
 +
| style="border-top:1px solid black" | &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{R4b.}\!</math>
 +
| <math>\downharpoonleft x \in Q \downharpoonright</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{R4c.}\!</math>
 +
| <math>\downharpoonleft x \in Q \downharpoonright (x)</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{R4d.}\!</math>
 +
| <math>\upharpoonleft Q \upharpoonright (x)</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|- style="height:40px"
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
| <math>\text{R4e.}\!</math>
 +
| <math>\upharpoonleft Q \upharpoonright (x) = \underline{1}</math>
 +
| &nbsp;
 +
|}
   −
and u C U is varied,
+
<br>
 
  −
then the following are equivalent:
  −
 
  −
R4a. u C X.
  −
 
  −
R4b. [u C X].
  −
 
  −
R4c. [u C X](u).
  −
 
  −
R4d. {X}(u).
  −
 
  −
R4e. {X}(u) = 1.
      +
<pre>
 
The first and last items on this list, namely, the sentences "u C X" and "{X}(u) = 1" that are annotated as "R4a" and "R4e", respectively, are just the pair of sentences from Rule 3 whose equivalence for all u C U is usually taken to define the idea of an indicator function {X} : U -> B.  At first sight, the inclusion of the other items appears to involve a category confusion, in other words, to mix the modes of interpretation and to create an array of mismatches between their own ostensible types and the ruling type of a sentence.  On reflection, and taken in context, these problems are not as serious as they initially seem.  For instance, the expression "[u C X]" ostensibly denotes a proposition, but if it does, then it evidently can be recognized, by virtue of this very fact, to be a genuine sentence.  As a general rule, if one can see it on the page, then it cannot be a proposition, but can be, at best, a sign of one.
 
The first and last items on this list, namely, the sentences "u C X" and "{X}(u) = 1" that are annotated as "R4a" and "R4e", respectively, are just the pair of sentences from Rule 3 whose equivalence for all u C U is usually taken to define the idea of an indicator function {X} : U -> B.  At first sight, the inclusion of the other items appears to involve a category confusion, in other words, to mix the modes of interpretation and to create an array of mismatches between their own ostensible types and the ruling type of a sentence.  On reflection, and taken in context, these problems are not as serious as they initially seem.  For instance, the expression "[u C X]" ostensibly denotes a proposition, but if it does, then it evidently can be recognized, by virtue of this very fact, to be a genuine sentence.  As a general rule, if one can see it on the page, then it cannot be a proposition, but can be, at best, a sign of one.
  
12,080

edits