Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{DISPLAYTITLE:Propositional Equation Reasoning Systems}} | | {{DISPLAYTITLE:Propositional Equation Reasoning Systems}} |
− | This article develops elementary facts about a family of formal calculi described as '''propositional equation reasoning systems''' ('''PERS'''). This work follows on the ''alpha graphs'' that [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] devised as a graphical syntax for [[propositional calculus]] and also on the ''calculus of indications'' that George Spencer Brown presented in his ''Laws of Form''. | + | '''Author: [[User:Jon Awbrey|Jon Awbrey]]''' |
− | <br clear="all">
| + | |
| + | This article develops elementary facts about a family of formal calculi described as '''propositional equation reasoning systems''' ('''PERS'''). This work follows on the ''alpha graphs'' that Charles Sanders Peirce devised as a graphical syntax for [[propositional calculus]] and also on the ''calculus of indications'' that George Spencer Brown presented in his ''Laws of Form''. |
| + | |
| ==Formal development== | | ==Formal development== |
| | | |
Line 8: |
Line 10: |
| ===Axioms=== | | ===Axioms=== |
| | | |
− | The axioms are just four in number, divided into the ''arithmetic initials'', <math>I_1\!</math> and <math>I_2\!</math>, and the ''algebraic initials'', <math>J_1\!</math> and <math>J_2\!</math>. | + | The axioms are just four in number, divided into the ''arithmetic initials'', <math>I_1\!</math> and <math>I_2,\!</math> and the ''algebraic initials'', <math>J_1\!</math> and <math>J_2.\!</math> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" |
Line 20: |
Line 22: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | One way of assigning logical meaning to the initial equations is known as the ''entitative interpretation'' (<math>\operatorname{En}</math>). Under <math>\operatorname{En}</math>, the axioms read as follows: | + | One way of assigning logical meaning to the initial equations is known as the ''entitative interpretation'' <math>(\mathrm{En}).\!</math> Under <math>\mathrm{En},\!</math> the axioms read as follows: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" |
Line 27: |
Line 29: |
| I_1 | | I_1 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | \operatorname{true} ~\operatorname{or}~ \operatorname{true} | + | \mathrm{true} ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{true} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{true} | + | \mathrm{true} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| I_2 | | I_2 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | \operatorname{not}~ \operatorname{true} | + | \mathrm{not}~ \mathrm{true} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{false} | + | \mathrm{false} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| J_1 | | J_1 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | a ~\operatorname{or}~ \operatorname{not}~ a | + | a ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{not}~ a |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{true} | + | \mathrm{true} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| J_2 | | J_2 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | (a ~\operatorname{or}~ b) ~\operatorname{and}~ (a ~\operatorname{or}~ c) | + | (a ~\mathrm{or}~ b) ~\mathrm{and}~ (a ~\mathrm{or}~ c) |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | a ~\operatorname{or}~ (b ~\operatorname{and}~ c) | + | a ~\mathrm{or}~ (b ~\mathrm{and}~ c) |
| \end{matrix}</math> | | \end{matrix}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Another way of assigning logical meaning to the initial equations is known as the ''existential interpretation'' (<math>\operatorname{Ex}</math>). Under <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math>, the axioms read as follows: | + | Another way of assigning logical meaning to the initial equations is known as the ''existential interpretation'' <math>(\mathrm{Ex}).\!</math> Under <math>\mathrm{Ex},\!</math> the axioms read as follows: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" |
Line 58: |
Line 60: |
| I_1 | | I_1 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | \operatorname{false} ~\operatorname{and}~ \operatorname{false} | + | \mathrm{false} ~\mathrm{and}~ \mathrm{false} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{false} | + | \mathrm{false} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| I_2 | | I_2 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | \operatorname{not}~ \operatorname{false} | + | \mathrm{not}~ \mathrm{false} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{true} | + | \mathrm{true} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| J_1 | | J_1 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | a ~\operatorname{and}~ \operatorname{not}~ a | + | a ~\mathrm{and}~ \mathrm{not}~ a |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{false} | + | \mathrm{false} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| J_2 | | J_2 |
| & : & | | & : & |
− | (a ~\operatorname{and}~ b) ~\operatorname{or}~ (a ~\operatorname{and}~ c) | + | (a ~\mathrm{and}~ b) ~\mathrm{or}~ (a ~\mathrm{and}~ c) |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | a ~\operatorname{and}~ (b ~\operatorname{or}~ c) | + | a ~\mathrm{and}~ (b ~\mathrm{or}~ c) |
| \end{matrix}</math> | | \end{matrix}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | All of the axioms in this set have the form of equations. This means that all of the inference licensed by them are reversible. The proof annotation scheme employed below makes use of a double bar <math>\overline{\underline{~~~~~~}}</math> to mark this fact, but it will often be left to the reader to decide which of the two possible ways of applying the axiom is the one that is called for in a particular case. | + | All of the axioms in this set have the form of equations. This means that all of the inference licensed by them are reversible. The proof annotation scheme employed below makes use of a double bar <math>\overline{\underline{15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)~}}\!</math> to mark this fact, but it will often be left to the reader to decide which of the two possible ways of applying the axiom is the one that is called for in a particular case. |
| | | |
− | Peirce introduced these formal equations at a level of abstraction that is one step higher than their customary interpretations as propositional calculi, which two readings he called the ''Entitative'' and the ''Existential'' interpretations, here referred to as <math>\operatorname{En}</math> and <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math>, respectively. The early CSP, as in his essay on “Qualitative Logic”, and also GSB, emphasized the <math>\operatorname{En}</math> interpretation, while the later CSP developed mostly the <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math> interpretation. | + | Peirce introduced these formal equations at a level of abstraction that is one step higher than their customary interpretations as propositional calculi, which two readings he called the ''Entitative'' and the ''Existential'' interpretations, here referred to as <math>\mathrm{En}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{Ex},\!</math> respectively. The early CSP, as in his essay on “Qualitative Logic”, and also GSB, emphasized the <math>\mathrm{En}\!</math> interpretation, while the later CSP developed mostly the <math>\mathrm{Ex}\!</math> interpretation. |
| | | |
| ===Frequently used theorems=== | | ===Frequently used theorems=== |
Line 90: |
Line 92: |
| ====C<sub>1</sub>. Double negation==== | | ====C<sub>1</sub>. Double negation==== |
| | | |
− | The first theorem goes under the names of ''Consequence 1'' <math>(C_1)\!</math>, the ''double negation theorem'' (DNT), or ''Reflection''. | + | The first theorem goes under the names of ''Consequence 1'' <math>(C_1),\!</math> the ''double negation theorem'' (DNT), or ''Reflection''. |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" |
Line 96: |
Line 98: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | The proof that follows is adapted from the one that was given by [[George Spencer Brown]] in his book ''Laws of Form'' (LOF) and credited to two of his students, John Dawes and D.A. Utting. | + | The proof that follows is adapted from the one that was given by George Spencer Brown in his book ''Laws of Form'' (LOF) and credited to two of his students, John Dawes and D.A. Utting. |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
Line 261: |
Line 263: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" |
− | | <math>((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Rightarrow p</math> | + | | <math>((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Rightarrow p\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 417: |
Line 419: |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 1.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 1.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Reflect ab, ac, bc.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Reflect ab, ac, bc ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 2.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 2.jpg|500px]] |
Line 425: |
Line 427: |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 3.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 3.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Collect ab, ac, bc.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Collect ab, ac, bc ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 4.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 4.jpg|500px]] |
Line 441: |
Line 443: |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 7.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 7.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Delete a, b, c.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Delete a, b, c ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 8.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Majority Function Example 2.0 Proof 1 Frame 8.jpg|500px]] |
Line 469: |
Line 471: |
| Let us now extend the CSP–GSB calculus in the following way: | | Let us now extend the CSP–GSB calculus in the following way: |
| | | |
− | The first extension is the ''reflective extension of logical graphs'', or what may be described as the ''cactus language'', after its principal graph-theoretic data structure. It is generated by generalizing the negation operator <math>\texttt{(\_)}</math> in a particular manner, treating <math>\texttt{(\_)}</math> as the ''[[minimal negation operator]]'' of order 1, and adding another such operator for each integer parameter greater than 1. Taken in series, the minimal negation operators are symbolized by parenthesized argument lists of the following shapes: <math>\texttt{(\_)},</math> <math>\texttt{(\_, \_)},</math> <math>\texttt{(\_, \_, \_)},</math> and so on, where the number of argument slots is the order of the reflective negation operator in question. | + | The first extension is the ''reflective extension of logical graphs'', or what may be described as the ''cactus language'', after its principal graph-theoretic data structure. It is generated by generalizing the negation operator <math>\texttt{(\_)}\!</math> in a particular manner, treating <math>\texttt{(\_)}\!</math> as the ''[[minimal negation operator]]'' of order 1, and adding another such operator for each integer parameter greater than 1. Taken in series, the minimal negation operators are symbolized by parenthesized argument lists of the following shapes: <math>\texttt{(\_)},\!</math> <math>\texttt{(\_, \_)},\!</math> <math>\texttt{(\_, \_, \_)},\!</math> and so on, where the number of argument slots is the order of the reflective negation operator in question. |
| | | |
| ===Fundamental evaluation rule=== | | ===Fundamental evaluation rule=== |
Line 475: |
Line 477: |
| The formal rule of evaluation for a <math>k\!</math>''-lobe'' or <math>k\!</math>-operator may be summarized as follows: | | The formal rule of evaluation for a <math>k\!</math>''-lobe'' or <math>k\!</math>-operator may be summarized as follows: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 510: |
Line 512: |
| These operators may be interpreted for logic as assertions about the values of their listed arguments, resulting in the following pair of dual interpretations. | | These operators may be interpreted for logic as assertions about the values of their listed arguments, resulting in the following pair of dual interpretations. |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 553: |
Line 555: |
| Three immediate corollaries of the fundamental evaluation rule are listed below for future reference. | | Three immediate corollaries of the fundamental evaluation rule are listed below for future reference. |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 569: |
Line 571: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 586: |
Line 588: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 623: |
Line 625: |
| I am going to revert to my customarily sloppy workshop manners and refer to propositions and proposition expressions on rough analogy with functions and function expressions, which implies that a proposition will be regarded as the chief formal object of discussion, enjoying many proposition expressions, formulas, or sentences that express it, but worst of all I will probably just go ahead and use any and all of these terms as loosely as I see fit, taking a bit of extra care only when I see the need. | | I am going to revert to my customarily sloppy workshop manners and refer to propositions and proposition expressions on rough analogy with functions and function expressions, which implies that a proposition will be regarded as the chief formal object of discussion, enjoying many proposition expressions, formulas, or sentences that express it, but worst of all I will probably just go ahead and use any and all of these terms as loosely as I see fit, taking a bit of extra care only when I see the need. |
| | | |
− | Let <math>Q\!</math> be a propositional expression with an unspecified, but context-appropriate number of variables, say, none, or <math>x\!</math>, or <math>x_1, \ldots, x_k\!</math>, as the case may be. | + | Let <math>Q\!</math> be a propositional expression with an unspecified, but context-appropriate number of variables, say, none, or <math>x,\!</math> or <math>x_1, \ldots, x_k,\!</math> as the case may be. |
| | | |
| :* Strings and graphs that have no labels are called ''bare''. | | :* Strings and graphs that have no labels are called ''bare''. |
− | :* A bare terminal node, symbolized by a small circle <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \circ {}^{\prime\prime}</math> in text, is known as a ''stone''. | + | :* A bare terminal node, symbolized by a small circle <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \circ {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> in text, is known as a ''stone''. |
− | :* A bare terminal edge, symbolized by a vertical bar <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \vert {}^{\prime\prime}</math> in text, is known as a ''stick''. | + | :* A bare terminal edge, symbolized by a vertical bar <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \vert {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> in text, is known as a ''stick''. |
| | | |
− | Let the ''replacement expression'' of the form <math>Q[\circ /x]</math> denote the proposition that results from <math>Q\!</math> by replacing every token of the variable <math>x\!</math> with a blank, that is to say, by erasing <math>x\!</math>. | + | Let the ''replacement expression'' of the form <math>Q[\circ /x]\!</math> denote the proposition that results from <math>Q\!</math> by replacing every token of the variable <math>x\!</math> with a blank, that is to say, by erasing <math>x.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | Let the ''replacement expression'' of the form <math>Q[\,\vert /x]</math> denote the proposition that results from <math>Q\!</math> by replacing every token of the variable <math>x\!</math> with a stick stemming from the site of <math>x\!</math>. | + | Let the ''replacement expression'' of the form <math>Q[\,\vert /x]\!</math> denote the proposition that results from <math>Q\!</math> by replacing every token of the variable <math>x\!</math> with a stick stemming from the site of <math>x.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | In the case of a propositional expression <math>Q\!</math> that has no token of the designated variable <math>x\!</math>, let it be stipulated that <math>Q[\circ /x] = Q = Q[\,\vert /x]</math>. | + | In the case of a propositional expression <math>Q\!</math> that has no token of the designated variable <math>x,\!</math> let it be stipulated that <math>Q[\circ /x] = Q = Q[\,\vert /x].\!</math> |
| | | |
| I think that I am at long last ready to state the following: | | I think that I am at long last ready to state the following: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 662: |
Line 664: |
| In order to think of tackling even the roughest sketch toward a proof of this theorem, we need to add a number of axioms and axiom schemata. Because I abandoned proof-theoretic purity somewhere in the middle of grinding this calculus into computational form, I never got around to finding the most elegant and minimal, or anything near a complete set of axioms for the ''cactus language'', so what I list here are just the slimmest rudiments of the hodge-podge of ''rules of thumb'' that I have found over time to be necessary and useful in most working settings. Some of these special precepts are probably provable from genuine axioms, but I have yet to go looking for a more proper formulation. | | In order to think of tackling even the roughest sketch toward a proof of this theorem, we need to add a number of axioms and axiom schemata. Because I abandoned proof-theoretic purity somewhere in the middle of grinding this calculus into computational form, I never got around to finding the most elegant and minimal, or anything near a complete set of axioms for the ''cactus language'', so what I list here are just the slimmest rudiments of the hodge-podge of ''rules of thumb'' that I have found over time to be necessary and useful in most working settings. Some of these special precepts are probably provable from genuine axioms, but I have yet to go looking for a more proper formulation. |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 741: |
Line 743: |
| Here is a proof sketch for the ''Case Analysis-Synthesis Theorem'' (CAST): | | Here is a proof sketch for the ''Case Analysis-Synthesis Theorem'' (CAST): |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 808: |
Line 810: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 02.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 02.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 03.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 03.jpg|500px]] |
Line 816: |
Line 818: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 04.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 04.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 05.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 05.jpg|500px]] |
Line 828: |
Line 830: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 07.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 07.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 08.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 08.jpg|500px]] |
Line 836: |
Line 838: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 09.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 09.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 10.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 10.jpg|500px]] |
Line 852: |
Line 854: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 13.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 13.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 14.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 14.jpg|500px]] |
Line 860: |
Line 862: |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 15.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 15.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cast C.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cast C ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 16.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof Praeclarum Theorema CAST 16.jpg|500px]] |
Line 895: |
Line 897: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Remembering that a blank node is the graphical equivalent of a logical value <math>\operatorname{true}</math>, the resulting DNF may be read as follows: | + | Remembering that a blank node is the graphical equivalent of a logical value <math>{\mathrm{true}},\!</math> the resulting DNF may be read as follows: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 935: |
Line 937: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" width="90%" |
− | | [[#Praeclarum_theorema|The first way of transforming the expression]] that appears on the left hand side of the equation can be described as ''proof-theoretic'' in character. | + | | [[#Praeclarum theorema|The first way of transforming the expression]] that appears on the left hand side of the equation can be described as ''proof-theoretic'' in character. |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[#Praeclarum_theorema_:_Proof_by_CAST|The second way of transforming the expression]] that appears on the left hand side of the equation can be described as ''model-theoretic'' in character. | + | | [[#Praeclarum theorema : Proof by CAST|The second way of transforming the expression]] that appears on the left hand side of the equation can be described as ''model-theoretic'' in character. |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 964: |
Line 966: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | For the sake of simplicity in discussing this example, let's stick with the existential interpretation (<math>\operatorname{Ex}</math>) of logical graphs and their corresponding parse strings. Under <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math> the formal expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> translates into the vernacular expression <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\operatorname{implies}~ q ~\operatorname{and}~ p ~\operatorname{implies}~ r {}^{\prime\prime},</math> in symbols, <math>(p \Rightarrow q) \land (p \Rightarrow r),</math> so this is the reading that we'll want to keep in mind for the present. Where brevity is required, we may refer to the propositional expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> under the name <math>f\!</math> by making use of the following definition: | + | For the sake of simplicity in discussing this example, let's stick with the existential interpretation <math>(\mathrm{Ex})\!</math> of logical graphs and their corresponding parse strings. Under <math>\mathrm{Ex}\!</math> the formal expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> translates into the vernacular expression <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\mathrm{implies}~ q ~\mathrm{and}~ p ~\mathrm{implies}~ r {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> in symbols, <math>(p \Rightarrow q) \land (p \Rightarrow r),\!</math> so this is the reading that we'll want to keep in mind for the present. Where brevity is required, we may refer to the propositional expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> under the name <math>f\!</math> by making use of the following definition: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
− | | <math>f ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>f ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Since the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> involves just three variables, it may be worth the trouble to draw a venn diagram of the situation. There are in fact two different ways to execute the picture. | + | Since the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> involves just three variables, it may be worth the trouble to draw a venn diagram of the situation. There are in fact two different ways to execute the picture. |
| | | |
− | Figure 2 indicates the points of the universe of discourse <math>X\!</math> for which the proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B}</math> has the value 1, here interpreted as the logical value <math>\operatorname{true}.</math> In this ''paint by numbers'' style of picture, one simply paints over the cells of a generic template for the universe <math>X,\!</math> going according to some previously adopted convention, for instance: Let the cells that get the value 0 under <math>f\!</math> remain untinted and let the cells that get the value 1 under <math>f\!</math> be painted or shaded. In doing this, it may be good to remind ourselves that the value of the picture as a whole is not in the ''paints'', in other words, the <math>0, 1\!</math> in <math>\mathbb{B},</math> but in the pattern of regions that they indicate. | + | Figure 2 indicates the points of the universe of discourse <math>X\!</math> for which the proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> has the value 1, here interpreted as the logical value <math>\mathrm{true}.\!</math> In this ''paint by numbers'' style of picture, one simply paints over the cells of a generic template for the universe <math>X,\!</math> going according to some previously adopted convention, for instance: Let the cells that get the value 0 under <math>f\!</math> remain untinted and let the cells that get the value 1 under <math>f\!</math> be painted or shaded. In doing this, it may be good to remind ourselves that the value of the picture as a whole is not in the ''paints'', in other words, the <math>0, 1\!</math> in <math>\mathbb{B},\!</math> but in the pattern of regions that they indicate. |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center" |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)) (P (R)).jpg|500px]] || (36) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)) (P (R)).jpg|500px]] || (36) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>\text{Venn Diagram for}~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>\text{Venn Diagram for}~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | There are a number of standard ways in mathematics and statistics for talking about the subset <math>W\!</math> of the functional domain <math>X\!</math> that gets painted with the value <math>z \in \mathbb{B}</math> by the indicator function <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B}.</math> The region <math>W \subseteq X</math> is called by a variety of names in different settings, for example, the ''antecedent'', the ''fiber'', the ''inverse image'', the ''level set'', or the ''pre-image'' in <math>X\!</math> of <math>z\!</math> under <math>f.\!</math> It is notated and defined as <math>W = f^{-1}(z).\!</math> Here, <math>f^{-1}\!</math> is called the ''converse relation'' or the ''inverse relation'' — it is not in general an inverse function — corresponding to the function <math>f.\!</math> Whenever possible in simple examples, we use lower case letters for functions <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},</math> and it is sometimes useful to employ capital letters for subsets of <math>X,\!</math> if possible, in such a way that <math>F\!</math> is the fiber of 1 under <math>f,\!</math> in other words, <math>F = f^{-1}(1).\!</math> | + | There are a number of standard ways in mathematics and statistics for talking about the subset <math>W\!</math> of the functional domain <math>X\!</math> that gets painted with the value <math>z \in \mathbb{B}\!</math> by the indicator function <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math> The region <math>W \subseteq X\!</math> is called by a variety of names in different settings, for example, the ''antecedent'', the ''fiber'', the ''inverse image'', the ''level set'', or the ''pre-image'' in <math>X\!</math> of <math>z\!</math> under <math>f.\!</math> It is notated and defined as <math>W = f^{-1}(z).\!</math> Here, <math>f^{-1}\!</math> is called the ''converse relation'' or the ''inverse relation'' — it is not in general an inverse function — corresponding to the function <math>f.\!</math> Whenever possible in simple examples, we use lower case letters for functions <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> and it is sometimes useful to employ capital letters for subsets of <math>X,\!</math> if possible, in such a way that <math>F\!</math> is the fiber of 1 under <math>f,\!</math> in other words, <math>F = f^{-1}(1).\!</math> |
| | | |
− | The easiest way to see the sense of the venn diagram is to notice that the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))},</math> read as <math>p \Rightarrow q,</math> can also be read as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \operatorname{not}~ p ~\operatorname{without}~ q {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> Its assertion effectively excludes any tincture of truth from the region of <math>P\!</math> that lies outside the region <math>Q.\!</math> In a similar manner, the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},</math> read as <math>p \Rightarrow r,</math> can also be read as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \operatorname{not}~ p ~\operatorname{without}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> Asserting it effectively excludes any tincture of truth from the region of <math>P\!</math> that lies outside the region <math>R.\!</math> | + | The easiest way to see the sense of the venn diagram is to notice that the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))},\!</math> read as <math>p \Rightarrow q,\!</math> can also be read as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{not}~ p ~\mathrm{without}~ q {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> Its assertion effectively excludes any tincture of truth from the region of <math>P\!</math> that lies outside the region <math>Q.\!</math> In a similar manner, the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},\!</math> read as <math>p \Rightarrow r,\!</math> can also be read as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{not}~ p ~\mathrm{without}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> Asserting it effectively excludes any tincture of truth from the region of <math>P\!</math> that lies outside the region <math>R.\!</math> |
| | | |
| Figure 3 shows the other standard way of drawing a venn diagram for such a proposition. In this ''punctured soap film'' style of picture — others may elect to give it the more dignified title of a ''logical quotient topology'' — one begins with Figure 31 and then proceeds to collapse the fiber of 0 under <math>X\!</math> down to the point of vanishing utterly from the realm of active contemplation, arriving at the following picture: | | Figure 3 shows the other standard way of drawing a venn diagram for such a proposition. In this ''punctured soap film'' style of picture — others may elect to give it the more dignified title of a ''logical quotient topology'' — one begins with Figure 31 and then proceeds to collapse the fiber of 0 under <math>X\!</math> down to the point of vanishing utterly from the realm of active contemplation, arriving at the following picture: |
Line 989: |
Line 991: |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q R)).jpg|500px]] || (37) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q R)).jpg|500px]] || (37) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>\text{Venn Diagram for}~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q ~ r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>\text{Venn Diagram for}~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q ~ r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 997: |
Line 999: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,003: |
Line 1,005: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
− | | <math>(p \Rightarrow q) \land (p \Rightarrow r),</math> | + | | <math>(p \Rightarrow q) \land (p \Rightarrow r),\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,009: |
Line 1,011: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,015: |
Line 1,017: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
− | | <math>p \Rightarrow (q \land r).</math> | + | | <math>p \Rightarrow (q \land r).\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,028: |
Line 1,030: |
| While we go through each of these ways let us keep one eye out for the character and the conduct of each type of proceeding as a semiotic process, that is, as an orbit, in this case discrete, through a locus of signs, in this case propositional expressions, and as it happens in this case, a sequence of transformations that perseveres in the denotative objective of each expression, that is, in the abstract proposition that it expresses, while it preserves the informed constraint on the universe of discourse that gives us one viable candidate for the informational content of each expression in the interpretive chain of sign metamorphoses. | | While we go through each of these ways let us keep one eye out for the character and the conduct of each type of proceeding as a semiotic process, that is, as an orbit, in this case discrete, through a locus of signs, in this case propositional expressions, and as it happens in this case, a sequence of transformations that perseveres in the denotative objective of each expression, that is, in the abstract proposition that it expresses, while it preserves the informed constraint on the universe of discourse that gives us one viable candidate for the informational content of each expression in the interpretive chain of sign metamorphoses. |
| | | |
− | A ''sign relation'' <math>L\!</math> is a subset of a cartesian product <math>O \times S \times I,</math> where <math>O, S, I\!</math> are sets known as the ''object'', ''sign'', and ''interpretant sign'' domains, respectively. These facts are symbolized by writing <math>L \subseteq O \times S \times I.</math> Accordingly, a sign relation <math>L\!</math> consists of ordered triples of the form <math>(o, s, i),\!</math> where <math>o, s, i\!</math> belong to the domains <math>O, S, I,\!</math> respectively. An ordered triple of the form <math>(o, s, i) \in L</math> is referred to as a ''sign triple'' or an ''elementary sign relation''. | + | A ''sign relation'' <math>L\!</math> is a subset of a cartesian product <math>O \times S \times I,\!</math> where <math>O, S, I\!</math> are sets known as the ''object'', ''sign'', and ''interpretant sign'' domains, respectively. These facts are symbolized by writing <math>L \subseteq O \times S \times I.\!</math> Accordingly, a sign relation <math>L\!</math> consists of ordered triples of the form <math>(o, s, i),\!</math> where <math>{o, s, i}\!</math> belong to the domains <math>{O, S, I},\!</math> respectively. An ordered triple of the form <math>(o, s, i) \in L\!</math> is referred to as a ''sign triple'' or an ''elementary sign relation''. |
| | | |
− | The ''syntactic domain'' of a sign relation <math>L \subseteq O \times S \times I</math> is defined as the set-theoretic union <math>S \cup I</math> of its sign domain <math>S\!</math> and its interpretant domain <math>I.\!</math> It is not uncommon, especially in formal examples, for the sign domain and the interpretant domain to be equal as sets, in short, to have <math>S = I.\!</math> | + | The ''syntactic domain'' of a sign relation <math>L \subseteq O \times S \times I\!</math> is defined as the set-theoretic union <math>S \cup I\!</math> of its sign domain <math>S\!</math> and its interpretant domain <math>I.\!</math> It is not uncommon, especially in formal examples, for the sign domain and the interpretant domain to be equal as sets, in short, to have <math>S = I.\!</math> |
| | | |
| Sign relations may contain any number of sign triples, finite or infinite. Finite sign relations do arise in applications and can be very instructive as expository examples, but most of the sign relations of significance in logic have infinite sign and interpretant domains, and usually infinite object domains, in the long run, at least, though one frequently works up to infinite domains by a series of finite approximations and gradual stages. | | Sign relations may contain any number of sign triples, finite or infinite. Finite sign relations do arise in applications and can be very instructive as expository examples, but most of the sign relations of significance in logic have infinite sign and interpretant domains, and usually infinite object domains, in the long run, at least, though one frequently works up to infinite domains by a series of finite approximations and gradual stages. |
Line 1,043: |
Line 1,045: |
| For some reason I always think of this as the way that our DNA would prove it. | | For some reason I always think of this as the way that our DNA would prove it. |
| | | |
− | We are in the process of examining various proofs of the propositional equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},</math> and viewing these proofs in the light of their character as semiotic processes, in essence, as sign-theoretic transformations. | + | We are in the process of examining various proofs of the propositional equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},\!</math> and viewing these proofs in the light of their character as semiotic processes, in essence, as sign-theoretic transformations. |
| | | |
| The second way of establishing the truth of this equation is one that I see, rather loosely, as ''model-theoretic'', for no better reason than the sense of its ending with a pattern of expression, a variant of the ''disjunctive normal form'' (DNF), that is commonly recognized to be the form that one extracts from a truth table by pulling out the rows of the table that evaluate to true and constructing the disjunctive expression that sums up the senses of the corresponding interpretations. | | The second way of establishing the truth of this equation is one that I see, rather loosely, as ''model-theoretic'', for no better reason than the sense of its ending with a pattern of expression, a variant of the ''disjunctive normal form'' (DNF), that is commonly recognized to be the form that one extracts from a truth table by pulling out the rows of the table that evaluate to true and constructing the disjunctive expression that sums up the senses of the corresponding interpretations. |
Line 1,061: |
Line 1,063: |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-2.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-2.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-3.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-3.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,077: |
Line 1,079: |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-6.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-6.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-7.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-1-7.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,094: |
Line 1,096: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | The final graph in the sequence of equivalents is a disjunctive normal form (DNF) for the proposition on the left hand side of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.</math> | + | The final graph in the sequence of equivalents is a disjunctive normal form (DNF) for the proposition on the left hand side of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.\!</math> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
Line 1,101: |
Line 1,103: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Remembering that a blank node is the graphical equivalent of a logical value <math>\operatorname{true},</math> the resulting DNF may be read as follows: | + | Remembering that a blank node is the graphical equivalent of a logical value <math>\mathrm{true},\!</math> the resulting DNF may be read as follows: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,120: |
Line 1,122: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | It remains to show that the right hand side of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}</math> is logically equivalent to the DNF just obtained. The needed chain of equations is as follows: | + | It remains to show that the right hand side of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}\!</math> is logically equivalent to the DNF just obtained. The needed chain of equations is as follows: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
Line 1,132: |
Line 1,134: |
| | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cast P.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cast P.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-2.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-2 ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-3.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-3.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,146: |
Line 1,148: |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-5.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-5.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-6.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 2-2-6 ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cancellation.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cancellation.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,167: |
Line 1,169: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | This is not only a logically equivalent DNF but exactly the same DNF expression that we obtained before, so we have established the given equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.</math> Incidentally, one may wish to note that this DNF expression quickly folds into the following form: | + | This is not only a logically equivalent DNF but exactly the same DNF expression that we obtained before, so we have established the given equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.\!</math> Incidentally, one may wish to note that this DNF expression quickly folds into the following form: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
Line 1,173: |
Line 1,175: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | This can be read to say <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \operatorname{either}~ p q r ~\operatorname{or}~ \operatorname{not}~ p {}^{\prime\prime},</math> which gives us yet another equivalent for the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> and the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.</math> Still another way of writing the same thing would be as follows: | + | This can be read to say <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{either}~ p q r ~\mathrm{or}~ \mathrm{not}~ p {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> which gives us yet another equivalent for the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> and the expression <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))}.\!</math> Still another way of writing the same thing would be as follows: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" |
Line 1,179: |
Line 1,181: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | In other words, <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\operatorname{is~equivalent~to}~ p ~\operatorname{and}~ q ~\operatorname{and}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> | + | In other words, <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\mathrm{is~equivalent~to}~ p ~\mathrm{and}~ q ~\mathrm{and}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | One lemma that suggests itself at this point is a principle that may be canonized as the ''Emptiness Rule''. It says that a bare lobe expression like <math>\texttt{( \_, \_, \ldots )},</math> with any number of places for arguments but nothing but blanks as filler, is logically tantamount to the proto-typical expression of its type, namely, the constant expression <math>\texttt{(~)}</math> that <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math> interprets as denoting the logical value <math>\operatorname{false}.</math> To depict the rule in graphical form, we have the continuing sequence of equations: | + | One lemma that suggests itself at this point is a principle that may be canonized as the ''Emptiness Rule''. It says that a bare lobe expression like <math>\texttt{( \_, \_, \ldots )},\!</math> with any number of places for arguments but nothing but blanks as filler, is logically tantamount to the proto-typical expression of its type, namely, the constant expression <math>\texttt{(~)}\!</math> that <math>\mathrm{Ex}\!</math> interprets as denoting the logical value <math>\mathrm{false}.\!</math> To depict the rule in graphical form, we have the continuing sequence of equations: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,201: |
Line 1,203: |
| Yet another rule that we'll need is the following: | | Yet another rule that we'll need is the following: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,220: |
Line 1,222: |
| This one is easy enough to derive from rules that are already known, but just for the sake of ready reference it is useful to canonize it as the ''Indistinctness Rule''. Finally, let me introduce a rule-of-thumb that is a bit more suited to routine computation, and that serves to replace the indistinctness rule in many cases where we actually have to call on it. This is actually just a special case of the evaluation rule listed above: | | This one is easy enough to derive from rules that are already known, but just for the sake of ready reference it is useful to canonize it as the ''Indistinctness Rule''. Finally, let me introduce a rule-of-thumb that is a bit more suited to routine computation, and that serves to replace the indistinctness rule in many cases where we actually have to call on it. This is actually just a special case of the evaluation rule listed above: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,249: |
Line 1,251: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | To continue with the beating of this still-kicking horse in the form of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},</math> let's now take up the third way that I mentioned for examining propositional equations, even if it is literally a third way only at the very outset, almost immediately breaking up according to whether one proceeds by way of the more routine model-theoretic path or else by way of the more strategic proof-theoretic path. | + | To continue with the beating of this still-kicking horse in the form of the equation <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q r \texttt{))},\!</math> let's now take up the third way that I mentioned for examining propositional equations, even if it is literally a third way only at the very outset, almost immediately breaking up according to whether one proceeds by way of the more routine model-theoretic path or else by way of the more strategic proof-theoretic path. |
| | | |
| Let's convert the equation between propositions: | | Let's convert the equation between propositions: |
Line 1,298: |
Line 1,300: |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-02.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-02.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-03.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-03.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,322: |
Line 1,324: |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-08.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-08.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Domination ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-09.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-09.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,344: |
Line 1,346: |
| | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cancellation.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Cancellation.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
− | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-14.jpg|500px]] | + | | [[Image:Proof (P (Q)) (P (R)) = (P (Q R)) 3-14 ISW.jpg|500px]] |
| |- | | |- |
| | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Emptiness.jpg|500px]] | | | [[Image:Equational Inference Bar -- Emptiness.jpg|500px]] |
Line 1,405: |
Line 1,407: |
| \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} | | \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} |
| {}^{\prime\prime} | | {}^{\prime\prime} |
− | \end{array}</math> | + | \end{array}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Under <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math> we have the following interpretations: | + | Under <math>\mathrm{Ex}\!</math> we have the following interpretations: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
− | | <math>e_0 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(~)} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> expresses the logical constant <math>\operatorname{false}.</math> | + | | <math>e_0 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(~)} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> expresses the logical constant <math>\mathrm{false}.\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>e_1 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{~} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> expresses the logical constant <math>\operatorname{true}.</math> | + | | <math>e_1 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{~} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> expresses the logical constant <math>\mathrm{true}.\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>e_2 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \operatorname{not}~ p ~\operatorname{without}~ q,</math> <math>\operatorname{and~not}~ p ~\operatorname{without}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> | + | | <math>e_2 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{not}~ p ~\mathrm{without}~ q,\!</math> <math>\mathrm{and~not}~ p ~\mathrm{without}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>e_3 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \operatorname{not}~ p ~\operatorname{without}~ q ~\operatorname{and}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> | + | | <math>e_3 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \mathrm{not}~ p ~\mathrm{without}~ q ~\mathrm{and}~ r {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>e_4 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\operatorname{and}~ q ~\operatorname{and}~ r,</math> <math>~\operatorname{or~else~not}~ p{}^{\prime\prime}.</math> | + | | <math>e_4 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> says <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p ~\mathrm{and}~ q ~\mathrm{and}~ r,\!</math> <math>~\mathrm{or~else~not}~ p{}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>e_5 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> says that <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> say the same thing. | + | | <math>e_5 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> says that <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> say the same thing. |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,427: |
Line 1,429: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))}.</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} = \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))}.\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,433: |
Line 1,435: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
− | | <math>s_1, s_2, s_3, \ldots, s_n.</math> | + | | <math>s_1, s_2, s_3, \ldots, s_n.\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
| '''Proof 1''' proceeded by the ''straightforward approach'', starting with <math>e_2\!</math> as <math>s_1\!</math> and ending with <math>e_3\!</math> as <math>s_n\!.</math> | | '''Proof 1''' proceeded by the ''straightforward approach'', starting with <math>e_2\!</math> as <math>s_1\!</math> and ending with <math>e_3\!</math> as <math>s_n\!.</math> |
| | | |
− | : That is, Proof 1 commenced from the sign <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> and ended up at the sign <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> by legal moves. | + | : That is, Proof 1 commenced from the sign <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> and ended up at the sign <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> by legal moves. |
| | | |
| '''Proof 2''' lit on by ''burning the candle at both ends'', changing <math>e_2\!</math> into a normal form that reduced to <math>e_4,\!</math> and changing <math>e_3\!</math> into a normal form that also reduced to <math>e_4,\!</math> in this way tethering <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> to a common stake. | | '''Proof 2''' lit on by ''burning the candle at both ends'', changing <math>e_2\!</math> into a normal form that reduced to <math>e_4,\!</math> and changing <math>e_3\!</math> into a normal form that also reduced to <math>e_4,\!</math> in this way tethering <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> to a common stake. |
| | | |
− | : Filling in the details, one route went from <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> to <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime},</math> and another went from <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> to <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime},</math> thus equating the two points of departure. | + | : Filling in the details, one route went from <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> to <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> and another went from <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> to <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p~q~r \texttt{~,~(} p \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> thus equating the two points of departure. |
| | | |
| '''Proof 3''' took the path of reflection, expressing the meta-equation between <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> in the form of the naturalized equation <math>e_5,\!</math> then taking <math>e_5\!</math> as <math>s_1\!</math> and exchanging it by dint of value preserving steps for <math>e_1\!</math> as <math>s_n.\!</math> | | '''Proof 3''' took the path of reflection, expressing the meta-equation between <math>e_2\!</math> and <math>e_3\!</math> in the form of the naturalized equation <math>e_5,\!</math> then taking <math>e_5\!</math> as <math>s_1\!</math> and exchanging it by dint of value preserving steps for <math>e_1\!</math> as <math>s_n.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | : This way of proceeding went from <math>e_5 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> to the blank expression that <math>\operatorname{Ex}</math> recognizes as the value <math>\operatorname{true}.</math> | + | : This way of proceeding went from <math>e_5 = {}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{((~(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))~,~(} p \texttt{~(} q~r \texttt{))~))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> to the blank expression that <math>\mathrm{Ex}\!</math> recognizes as the value <math>{\mathrm{true}}.\!</math> |
| | | |
| ==Computation and inference as semiosis== | | ==Computation and inference as semiosis== |
Line 1,471: |
Line 1,473: |
| ~ p | | ~ p |
| \\ | | \\ |
− | \overline{~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~} | + | \overline{15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| ~ q | | ~ q |
Line 1,504: |
Line 1,506: |
| ~ \textit{Expression~2} | | ~ \textit{Expression~2} |
| \\ | | \\ |
− | \overline{~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~} | + | \overline{15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| ~ \textit{Expression~3} | | ~ \textit{Expression~3} |
Line 1,510: |
Line 1,512: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | The expressions above the line are called ''premisses'' and the expression below the line is called a ''conclusion''. If the rule of inference is simple enough, the ''proof-theoretic turnstile symbol'' <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \vdash {}^{\prime\prime}</math> may be used to write the rule on a single line, as follows: | + | The expressions above the line are called ''premisses'' and the expression below the line is called a ''conclusion''. If the rule of inference is simple enough, the ''proof-theoretic turnstile symbol'' <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \vdash {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> may be used to write the rule on a single line, as follows: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
| | | | | |
− | <math>\textit{Premiss~1}, \textit{Premiss~2} ~\vdash~ \textit{Conclusion}.</math> | + | <math>\textit{Premiss~1}, \textit{Premiss~2} ~\vdash~ \textit{Conclusion}.\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,521: |
Line 1,523: |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
| | | | | |
− | From <math>\textit{Expression~1}</math> and <math>\textit{Expression~2}</math> infer <math>\textit{Expression~3}.</math> | + | From <math>{\textit{Expression~1}}\!</math> and <math>{\textit{Expression~2}}\!</math> infer <math>{\textit{Expression~3}}.\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Looking to Example 1, the rule of inference known as ''modus ponens'' says the following: From the premiss <math>p \Rightarrow q</math> and the premiss <math>p\!</math> one may logically infer the conclusion <math>q.\!</math> | + | Looking to Example 1, the rule of inference known as ''modus ponens'' says the following: From the premiss <math>p \Rightarrow q\!</math> and the premiss <math>p\!</math> one may logically infer the conclusion <math>q.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | Modus ponens is an ''illative'' or ''implicational'' rule. Passage through its turnstile incurs the toll of some information loss, and thus from a fact of <math>q\!</math> alone one cannot infer with any degree of certainty that <math>p \Rightarrow q</math> and <math>p\!</math> are the reasons why <math>q\!</math> happens to be true. | + | Modus ponens is an ''illative'' or ''implicational'' rule. Passage through its turnstile incurs the toll of some information loss, and thus from a fact of <math>q\!</math> alone one cannot infer with any degree of certainty that <math>p \Rightarrow q\!</math> and <math>p\!</math> are the reasons why <math>q\!</math> happens to be true. |
| | | |
− | Further considerations along these lines may lead us to appreciate the difference between ''implicational rules of inference'' and ''equational rules of inference'', the latter indicated by an ''equational line of inference'' or a 2-way turnstile <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \Vdash {}^{\prime\prime}.</math> | + | Further considerations along these lines may lead us to appreciate the difference between ''implicational rules of inference'' and ''equational rules of inference'', the latter indicated by an ''equational line of inference'' or a 2-way turnstile <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \Vdash {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math> |
| | | |
| ==Variations on a theme of transitivity== | | ==Variations on a theme of transitivity== |
Line 1,534: |
Line 1,536: |
| The next Example is extremely important, and for reasons that reach well beyond the level of propositional calculus as it is ordinarily conceived. But it's slightly tricky to get all of the details right, so it will be worth taking the trouble to look at it from several different angles and as it appears in diverse frames, genres, or styles of representation. | | The next Example is extremely important, and for reasons that reach well beyond the level of propositional calculus as it is ordinarily conceived. But it's slightly tricky to get all of the details right, so it will be worth taking the trouble to look at it from several different angles and as it appears in diverse frames, genres, or styles of representation. |
| | | |
− | In discussing this Example, it is useful to observe that the implication relation indicated by the propositional form <math>x \Rightarrow y</math> is equivalent to an order relation <math>x \le y</math> on the boolean values <math>0, 1 \in \mathbb{B},</math> where <math>0\!</math> is taken to be less than <math>1.\!</math> | + | In discussing this Example, it is useful to observe that the implication relation indicated by the propositional form <math>x \Rightarrow y\!</math> is equivalent to an order relation <math>x \le y\!</math> on the boolean values <math>0, 1 \in \mathbb{B},\!</math> where <math>0\!</math> is taken to be less than <math>1.\!</math> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
Line 1,553: |
Line 1,555: |
| ~ q \le r | | ~ q \le r |
| \\ | | \\ |
− | \overline{~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~} | + | \overline{15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| ~ p \le r | | ~ p \le r |
Line 1,577: |
Line 1,579: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | In stating the information-preserving analogue of transitivity, I have taken advantage of a common idiom in the use of order relation symbols, one that represents their logical conjunction by way of a concatenated syntax. Thus, <math>p \le q \le r</math> means <math>p \le q ~\operatorname{and}~ q \le r.</math> The claim that this 3-adic order relation holds among the three propositions <math>p, q, r\!</math> is a stronger claim — conveys more information — than the claim that the 2-adic relation <math>p \le r</math> holds between the two propositions <math>p\!</math> and <math>r.\!</math> | + | In stating the information-preserving analogue of transitivity, I have taken advantage of a common idiom in the use of order relation symbols, one that represents their logical conjunction by way of a concatenated syntax. Thus, <math>p \le q \le r\!</math> means <math>p \le q ~\mathrm{and}~ q \le r.\!</math> The claim that this 3-adic order relation holds among the three propositions <math>p, q, r\!</math> is a stronger claim — conveys more information — than the claim that the 2-adic relation <math>p \le r\!</math> holds between the two propositions <math>p\!</math> and <math>r.\!</math> |
| | | |
| To study the differences between these two versions of transitivity within what is locally a familiar context, let's view the propositional forms involved as if they were elementary cellular automaton rules, resulting in the following Table. | | To study the differences between these two versions of transitivity within what is locally a familiar context, let's view the propositional forms involved as if they were elementary cellular automaton rules, resulting in the following Table. |
Line 1,584: |
Line 1,586: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | | {| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="text-align:center; width:90%" |
− | |+ <math>\text{Table 51.}~~\text{Composite and Compiled Order Relations}</math> | + | |+ <math>\text{Table 51.}~~\text{Composite and Compiled Order Relations}\!</math> |
| |- style="background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="background:#f0f0ff" |
| | | | | |
− | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_1</math></p> | + | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_1\!</math></p> |
− | <p><math>\text{Decimal}</math></p> | + | <p><math>\text{Decimal}\!</math></p> |
| | | | | |
− | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_2</math></p> | + | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_2\!</math></p> |
− | <p><math>\text{Binary}</math></p> | + | <p><math>\text{Binary}\!</math></p> |
| | | | | |
− | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_3</math></p> | + | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_3\!</math></p> |
− | <p><math>\text{Vector}</math></p> | + | <p><math>\text{Vector}\!</math></p> |
| | | | | |
− | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_4</math></p> | + | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_4\!</math></p> |
− | <p><math>\text{Cactus}</math></p> | + | <p><math>\text{Cactus}\!</math></p> |
| | | | | |
− | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_5</math></p> | + | <p><math>\mathcal{L}_5\!</math></p> |
− | <p><math>\text{Order}</math></p> | + | <p><math>\text{Order}\!</math></p> |
| |- style="background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="background:#f0f0ff" |
| | | | | |
| | align="right" | <math>p\colon\!</math> | | | align="right" | <math>p\colon\!</math> |
− | | <math>1~1~1~1~0~0~0~0</math> | + | | <math>1~1~1~1~0~0~0~0\!</math> |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
Line 1,610: |
Line 1,612: |
| | | | | |
| | align="right" | <math>q\colon\!</math> | | | align="right" | <math>q\colon\!</math> |
− | | <math>1~1~0~0~1~1~0~0</math> | + | | <math>1~1~0~0~1~1~0~0\!</math> |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
Line 1,616: |
Line 1,618: |
| | | | | |
| | align="right" | <math>r\colon\!</math> | | | align="right" | <math>r\colon\!</math> |
− | | <math>1~0~1~0~1~0~1~0</math> | + | | <math>1~0~1~0~1~0~1~0\!</math> |
| | | | | |
| | | | | |
Line 1,679: |
Line 1,681: |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)).jpg|500px]] || (52) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)).jpg|500px]] || (52) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>f_{207}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>f_{207}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
| | | | | |
Line 1,685: |
Line 1,687: |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (Q (R)).jpg|500px]] || (53) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (Q (R)).jpg|500px]] || (53) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>f_{187}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>f_{187}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
| | | | | |
Line 1,691: |
Line 1,693: |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (R)).jpg|500px]] || (54) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (R)).jpg|500px]] || (54) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>f_{175}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>f_{175}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
| | | | | |
Line 1,697: |
Line 1,699: |
| | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)) (Q (R)).jpg|500px]] || (55) | | | [[Image:Venn Diagram (P (Q)) (Q (R)).jpg|500px]] || (55) |
| |- | | |- |
− | | <math>f_{139}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>f_{139}(p, q, r) ~=~ \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Among other things, these images make it visually obvious that the constraint on the three boolean variables <math>p, q, r\!</math> that is indicated by asserting either of the forms <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> or <math>p \le q \le r</math> implies a constraint on the two boolean variables <math>p, r\!</math> that is indicated by either of the forms <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> or <math>p \le r,</math> but that it imposes additional constraints on these variables that are not captured by the illative conclusion. | + | Among other things, these images make it visually obvious that the constraint on the three boolean variables <math>p, q, r\!</math> that is indicated by asserting either of the forms <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> or <math>p \le q \le r\!</math> implies a constraint on the two boolean variables <math>p, r\!</math> that is indicated by either of the forms <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> or <math>p \le r,\!</math> but that it imposes additional constraints on these variables that are not captured by the illative conclusion. |
| | | |
− | One way to view a proposition <math>f : \mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B}</math> is to consider its ''fiber of truth'', <math>f^{-1}(1) \subseteq \mathbb{B}^k,</math> and to regard it as a <math>k\!</math>-adic relation <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^k.</math> | + | One way to view a proposition <math>f : \mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> is to consider its ''fiber of truth'', <math>f^{-1}(1) \subseteq \mathbb{B}^k,\!</math> and to regard it as a <math>k\!</math>-adic relation <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^k.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | By way of general definition, the ''fiber'' of a function <math>f : X \to Y</math> at a given value <math>y\!</math> of its co-domain <math>Y\!</math> is the ''antecedent'' (also known as the ''inverse image'' or ''pre-image'') of <math>y\!</math> under <math>f.\!</math> This is a subset, possibly empty, of the domain <math>X,\!</math> notated as <math>f^{-1}(y) \subseteq X.</math> | + | By way of general definition, the ''fiber'' of a function <math>f : X \to Y\!</math> at a given value <math>y\!</math> of its co-domain <math>Y\!</math> is the ''antecedent'' (also known as the ''inverse image'' or ''pre-image'') of <math>y\!</math> under <math>f.\!</math> This is a subset, possibly empty, of the domain <math>X,\!</math> notated as <math>f^{-1}(y) \subseteq X.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | In particular, if <math>f\!</math> is a proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},</math> then the fiber of truth <math>f^{-1}(1)\!</math> is the subset of <math>X\!</math> that is ''indicated'' by the proposition <math>f.\!</math> Whenever we ''assert'' a proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},</math> we are saying that what it indicates is all that happens to be the case in the relevant universe of discourse <math>X.\!</math> Because the fiber of truth is used so often in logical contexts, it is convenient to define the more compact notation <math>[| f |] = f^{-1}(1).\!</math> | + | In particular, if <math>f\!</math> is a proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> then the fiber of truth <math>f^{-1}(1)\!</math> is the subset of <math>X\!</math> that is ''indicated'' by the proposition <math>f.\!</math> Whenever we ''assert'' a proposition <math>f : X \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> we are saying that what it indicates is all that happens to be the case in the relevant universe of discourse <math>X.\!</math> Because the fiber of truth is used so often in logical contexts, it is convenient to define the more compact notation <math>[| f |] = f^{-1}(1).\!</math> |
| | | |
− | Using this panoply of notions and notations, we may treat the fiber of truth of each proposition <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> as if it were a relational data table of the shape <math>\{ (p, q, r) \} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,</math> where the triples <math>(p, q, r)\!</math> are bit-tuples indicated by the proposition <math>f.\!</math> | + | Using this panoply of notions and notations, we may treat the fiber of truth of each proposition <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> as if it were a relational data table of the shape <math>\{ (p, q, r) \} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,\!</math> where the triples <math>(p, q, r)\!</math> are bit-tuples indicated by the proposition <math>f.\!</math> |
| | | |
| Thus we obtain the following four relational data tables for the propositions that we are looking at in Example 2. | | Thus we obtain the following four relational data tables for the propositions that we are looking at in Example 2. |
Line 1,715: |
Line 1,717: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 56.} ~~ [| f_{207} |] ~=~ [| p \le q |]</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 56.} ~~ [| f_{207} |] ~=~ [| p \le q |]\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
| | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> | | | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> |
Line 1,737: |
Line 1,739: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 57.} ~~ [| f_{187} |] ~=~ [| q \le r |]</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 57.} ~~ [| f_{187} |] ~=~ [| q \le r |]\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
| | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> | | | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> |
Line 1,759: |
Line 1,761: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 58.} ~~ [| f_{175} |] ~=~ [| p \le r |]</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 58.} ~~ [| f_{175} |] ~=~ [| p \le r |]\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
| | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> | | | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> |
Line 1,781: |
Line 1,783: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 59.} ~~ [| f_{139} |] ~=~ [| p \le q \le r |]</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 59.} ~~ [| f_{139} |] ~=~ [| p \le q \le r |]\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
| | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> | | | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> |
Line 1,804: |
Line 1,806: |
| For example, we considered the brands of ''information fusion'' that are involved in a couple of standard rules of inference, taken in both their equational and their illative variants. | | For example, we considered the brands of ''information fusion'' that are involved in a couple of standard rules of inference, taken in both their equational and their illative variants. |
| | | |
− | In particular, let us assume that we begin from a state of uncertainty about the universe of discourse <math>X = \mathbb{B}^3</math> that is standardly represented by a uniform distribution <math>u : X \to \mathbb{B}</math> such that <math>u(x) = 1\!</math> for all <math>x\!</math> in <math>X,\!</math> in short, by the constant proposition <math>1 : X \to \mathbb{B}.</math> This amounts to the ''maximum entropy sign state'' (MESS). As a measure of uncertainty, let us use either the multiplicative measure given by the cardinality of <math>X,\!</math> commonly notated as <math>|X|,\!</math> or else the additive measure given by <math>\log_2 |X|.\!</math> In this frame we have <math>|X| = 8\!</math> and <math>\log_2 |X| = 3,\!</math> to wit, 3 bits of doubt. | + | In particular, let us assume that we begin from a state of uncertainty about the universe of discourse <math>X = \mathbb{B}^3\!</math> that is standardly represented by a uniform distribution <math>u : X \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> such that <math>u(x) = 1\!</math> for all <math>x\!</math> in <math>X,\!</math> in short, by the constant proposition <math>1 : X \to \mathbb{B}.\!</math> This amounts to the ''maximum entropy sign state'' (MESS). As a measure of uncertainty, let us use either the multiplicative measure given by the cardinality of <math>X,\!</math> commonly notated as <math>|X|,\!</math> or else the additive measure given by <math>{\log_2 |X|}.\!</math> In this frame we have <math>{|X| = 8}\!</math> and <math>{\log_2 |X| = 3},\!</math> to wit, 3 bits of doubt. |
| | | |
| Let us now consider the various rules of inference for transitivity in the light of their performance as information-developing actions. | | Let us now consider the various rules of inference for transitivity in the light of their performance as information-developing actions. |
Line 1,820: |
Line 1,822: |
| ~ q \le r | | ~ q \le r |
| \\ | | \\ |
− | \overline{~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~} | + | \overline{15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)15:22, 6 November 2016 (UTC)} |
| \\ | | \\ |
| ~ p \le r | | ~ p \le r |
Line 1,826: |
Line 1,828: |
| |- | | |- |
| | valign="top" | <big>•</big> | | | valign="top" | <big>•</big> |
− | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>p \le q</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. | + | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>p \le q\!</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. |
| |- | | |- |
| | valign="top" | <big>•</big> | | | valign="top" | <big>•</big> |
− | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>q \le r</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. | + | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>q \le r\!</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. |
| |- | | |- |
| | valign="top" | <big>•</big> | | | valign="top" | <big>•</big> |
− | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>p \le r</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. | + | | colspan="3" | By itself, the information <math>p \le r\!</math> would reduce our uncertainty from <math>\log 8\!</math> bits to <math>\log 6\!</math> bits. |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | In this situation the application of the implicational rule of inference for transitivity to the information <math>p \le q</math> and the information <math>q \le r</math> to get the information <math>p \le r</math> does not increase the measure of information beyond what any one of the three propositions has independently of the other two. In a sense, then, the implicational rule operates only to move the information around without changing its measure in the slightest bit. | + | In this situation the application of the implicational rule of inference for transitivity to the information <math>p \le q\!</math> and the information <math>q \le r\!</math> to get the information <math>p \le r\!</math> does not increase the measure of information beyond what any one of the three propositions has independently of the other two. In a sense, then, the implicational rule operates only to move the information around without changing its measure in the slightest bit. |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="4" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="4" width="90%" |
Line 1,855: |
Line 1,857: |
| |- | | |- |
| | valign="top" | <big>•</big> | | | valign="top" | <big>•</big> |
− | | colspan="3" | The contents and the measures of information that are associated with the propositions <math>p \le q</math> and <math>q \le r</math> are the same as before. | + | | colspan="3" | The contents and the measures of information that are associated with the propositions <math>p \le q\!</math> and <math>q \le r\!</math> are the same as before. |
| |- | | |- |
| | valign="top" | <big>•</big> | | | valign="top" | <big>•</big> |
− | | colspan="3" | On its own, the information <math>p \le q \le r</math> would reduce our uncertainty from log(8) = 3 bits to log(4) = 2 bits, a reduction of 1 bit. | + | | colspan="3" | On its own, the information <math>p \le q \le r\!</math> would reduce our uncertainty from log(8) = 3 bits to log(4) = 2 bits, a reduction of 1 bit. |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
| These are just some of the initial observations that can be made about the dimensions of information and uncertainty in the conduct of logical inference, and there are many issues to be taken up as we get to the thick of it. In particular, we are taking propositions far too literally at the outset, reading their spots at face value, as it were, without yet considering their species character as fallible signs. | | These are just some of the initial observations that can be made about the dimensions of information and uncertainty in the conduct of logical inference, and there are many issues to be taken up as we get to the thick of it. In particular, we are taking propositions far too literally at the outset, reading their spots at face value, as it were, without yet considering their species character as fallible signs. |
| | | |
− | For ease of reference in the rest of this discussion, let us refer to the propositional form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> such that <math>f(p, q, r) = f_{139}(p, q, r) = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}</math> as the ''syllogism map'', written as <math>\operatorname{syll} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B},</math> and let us refer to its fiber of truth <math>[| \operatorname{syll} |] = \operatorname{syll}^{-1}(1)</math> as the ''syllogism relation'', written as <math>\operatorname{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3.</math> Table 60 shows <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> as a relational dataset. | + | For ease of reference in the rest of this discussion, let us refer to the propositional form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> such that <math>f(p, q, r) = f_{139}(p, q, r) = \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> as the ''syllogism map'', written as <math>\mathrm{syll} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> and let us refer to its fiber of truth <math>[| \mathrm{syll} |] = \mathrm{syll}^{-1}(1)\!</math> as the ''syllogism relation'', written as <math>\mathrm{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3.\!</math> Table 60 shows <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> as a relational dataset. |
| | | |
| <br> | | <br> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="border-left:1px solid black; border-top:1px solid black; border-right:1px solid black; border-bottom:1px solid black; text-align:center; width:40%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 60.} ~~ \text{Syllogism Relation}</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 60.} ~~ \text{Syllogism Relation}\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
| | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> | | | style="border-bottom:1px solid black" | <math>p\!</math> |
Line 1,885: |
Line 1,887: |
| <br> | | <br> |
| | | |
− | One of the first questions that we might ask about a 3-adic relation, in this case <math>\operatorname{Syll},</math> is whether it is ''determined by'' its 2-adic projections. I will illustrate what this means in the present case. | + | One of the first questions that we might ask about a 3-adic relation, in this case <math>\mathrm{Syll},\!</math> is whether it is ''determined by'' its 2-adic projections. I will illustrate what this means in the present case. |
| | | |
− | Table 61 repeats the relation <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> in the first column, listing its 3-tuples in bit-string form, followed by the 2-adic or ''planar'' projections of <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> in the next three columns. For instance, <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{pq}</math> is the 2-adic projection of <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> on the <math>pq\!</math> plane that is arrived at by deleting the <math>r\!</math> column and counting each 2-tuple that results just one time. Likewise, <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{pr}</math> is obtained by deleting the <math>q\!</math> column and <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{qr}</math> is derived by deleting the <math>p\!</math> column, ignoring whatever duplicate pairs may result. The final row of the right three columns gives the propositions of the form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}</math> that indicate the 2-adic relations that result from these projections. | + | Table 61 repeats the relation <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> in the first column, listing its 3-tuples in bit-string form, followed by the 2-adic or ''planar'' projections of <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> in the next three columns. For instance, <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{pq}\!</math> is the 2-adic projection of <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> on the <math>pq\!</math> plane that is arrived at by deleting the <math>r\!</math> column and counting each 2-tuple that results just one time. Likewise, <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{pr}\!</math> is obtained by deleting the <math>q\!</math> column and <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{qr}\!</math> is derived by deleting the <math>p\!</math> column, ignoring whatever duplicate pairs may result. The final row of the right three columns gives the propositions of the form <math>f : \mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> that indicate the 2-adic relations that result from these projections. |
| | | |
| <br> | | <br> |
| | | |
| {| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="text-align:center; width:80%" | | {| align="center" border="1" cellpadding="8" cellspacing="0" style="text-align:center; width:80%" |
− | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 61.} ~~ \text{Dyadic Projections of the Syllogism Relation}</math> | + | |+ style="height:30px" | <math>\text{Table 61.} ~~ \text{Dyadic Projections of the Syllogism Relation}\!</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
− | | <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> | + | | <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> |
− | | <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{pq}</math> | + | | <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{pq}\!</math> |
− | | <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{pr}</math> | + | | <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{pr}\!</math> |
− | | <math>\operatorname{Syll}_{qr}</math> | + | | <math>\mathrm{Syll}_{qr}\!</math> |
| |- | | |- |
| | | | | |
Line 1,916: |
Line 1,918: |
| \end{matrix}</math> | | \end{matrix}</math> |
| |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" | | |- style="height:40px; background:#f0f0ff" |
− | | <math>p \le q \le r</math> | + | | <math>p \le q \le r\!</math> |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))}\!</math> |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
− | | <math>\texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}</math> | + | | <math>\texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
Line 1,934: |
Line 1,936: |
| The contrast between the information destroying and the information preserving versions of the transitive rule of inference led us to examine the relationships among several boolean functions, namely, those that qualify locally as the elementary cellular automata rules <math>f_{139}, f_{175}, f_{187}, f_{207}.\!</math> | | The contrast between the information destroying and the information preserving versions of the transitive rule of inference led us to examine the relationships among several boolean functions, namely, those that qualify locally as the elementary cellular automata rules <math>f_{139}, f_{175}, f_{187}, f_{207}.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | The function <math>f_{139} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> and its fiber <math>[| f_{139} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3</math> appeared to be key to many structures in this setting, and so I singled them out under the new names of <math>\operatorname{syll} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> and <math>\operatorname{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,</math> respectively. | + | The function <math>f_{139} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and its fiber <math>[| f_{139} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3\!</math> appeared to be key to many structures in this setting, and so I singled them out under the new names of <math>\mathrm{syll} : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and <math>\mathrm{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,\!</math> respectively. |
| | | |
| Managing the conceptual complexity of our considerations at this juncture put us in need of some conceptual tools that I broke off to develop in my notes on "Reductions Among Relations". The main items that we need right away from that thread are the definitions of relational projections and their inverses, the tacit extensions. | | Managing the conceptual complexity of our considerations at this juncture put us in need of some conceptual tools that I broke off to develop in my notes on "Reductions Among Relations". The main items that we need right away from that thread are the definitions of relational projections and their inverses, the tacit extensions. |
Line 1,940: |
Line 1,942: |
| But the more I survey the problem setting the more it looks like we need better ways to bring our visual intuitions to play on the scene, and so let us next lay out some visual schemata that are designed to facilitate that. | | But the more I survey the problem setting the more it looks like we need better ways to bring our visual intuitions to play on the scene, and so let us next lay out some visual schemata that are designed to facilitate that. |
| | | |
− | Figure 62 shows the familiar picture of a boolean 3-cube, where the points of <math>\mathbb{B}^3</math> are coordinated as bit strings of length three. Looking at the functions <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> and the relations <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3</math> on this pattern, one views the construction of either type of object as a matter of coloring the nodes of the 3-cube with choices from a pair of colors that stipulate which points are in the relation <math>L = [| f |]\!</math> and which points are out of it. Bowing to common convention, we may use the color <math>1\!</math> for points that are ''in'' a given relation and the color <math>0\!</math> for points that are ''out'' of the same relation. However, it will be more convenient here to indicate the former case by writing the coordinates in the place of the node and to indicate the latter case by plotting the point as an unlabeled node "o". | + | Figure 62 shows the familiar picture of a boolean 3-cube, where the points of <math>\mathbb{B}^3\!</math> are coordinated as bit strings of length three. Looking at the functions <math>f : \mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and the relations <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3\!</math> on this pattern, one views the construction of either type of object as a matter of coloring the nodes of the 3-cube with choices from a pair of colors that stipulate which points are in the relation <math>{L = [| f |]}\!</math> and which points are out of it. Bowing to common convention, we may use the color <math>1\!</math> for points that are ''in'' a given relation and the color <math>0\!</math> for points that are ''out'' of the same relation. However, it will be more convenient here to indicate the former case by writing the coordinates in the place of the node and to indicate the latter case by plotting the point as an unlabeled node "o". |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,979: |
Line 1,981: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | Table 63 shows the 3-adic relation <math>\operatorname{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3</math> again, and Figure 64 shows it plotted on a 3-cube template. | + | Table 63 shows the 3-adic relation <math>\mathrm{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3\!</math> again, and Figure 64 shows it plotted on a 3-cube template. |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 1,995: |
Line 1,997: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (63) | | | (63) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,032: |
Line 2,036: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | We return once more to the plane projections of <math>\operatorname{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3.</math> | + | We return once more to the plane projections of <math>\mathrm{Syll} \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,048: |
Line 2,052: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (65) | | | (65) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,067: |
Line 2,073: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | In showing the 2-adic projections of a 3-adic relation <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,</math> I will translate the coordinates of the points in each relation to the plane of the projection, there dotting out with a dot "." the bit of the bit string that is out of place on that plane. | + | In showing the 2-adic projections of a 3-adic relation <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}^3,\!</math> I will translate the coordinates of the points in each relation to the plane of the projection, there dotting out with a dot "." the bit of the bit string that is out of place on that plane. |
| | | |
− | Figure 67 shows <math>\operatorname{Syll}</math> and its three 2-adic projections: | + | Figure 67 shows <math>\mathrm{Syll}\!</math> and its three 2-adic projections: |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,130: |
Line 2,136: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | We now compute the tacit extensions of the 2-adic projections of <math>\operatorname{Syll},</math> alias <math>f_{139},\!</math> and this makes manifest its relationship to the other functions and fibers, namely, <math>f_{175}, f_{187}, f_{207}.\!</math> | + | We now compute the tacit extensions of the 2-adic projections of <math>\mathrm{Syll},\!</math> alias <math>f_{139},\!</math> and this makes manifest its relationship to the other functions and fibers, namely, <math>f_{175}, f_{187}, f_{207}.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,146: |
Line 2,152: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (68) | | | (68) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,163: |
Line 2,171: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (69) | | | (69) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,185: |
Line 2,195: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (70) | | | (70) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,230: |
Line 2,242: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (71) | | | (71) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,284: |
Line 2,298: |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| | (72) | | | (72) |
− | |- | + | |} |
| + | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,336: |
Line 2,352: |
| | | | | |
| <math>\begin{array}{lcc} | | <math>\begin{array}{lcc} |
− | \operatorname{Syll} | + | \mathrm{Syll} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{te}(\operatorname{Syll}_{12}) | + | \mathrm{te}(\mathrm{Syll}_{12}) |
| \cap | | \cap |
− | \operatorname{te}(\operatorname{Syll}_{23}) | + | \mathrm{te}(\mathrm{Syll}_{23}) |
| \\[6pt] | | \\[6pt] |
− | \operatorname{Syll}_{13} | + | \mathrm{Syll}_{13} |
| & = & | | & = & |
− | \operatorname{Syll}_{12} | + | \mathrm{Syll}_{12} |
| \circ | | \circ |
− | \operatorname{Syll}_{23} | + | \mathrm{Syll}_{23} |
| \end{array}</math> | | \end{array}</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | {| align="center" cellpadding="10" style="text-align:center; width:90%" | + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| | | | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
Line 2,413: |
Line 2,429: |
| In accord with my experimental way, I will stick with the case of transitive inference until I have pinned it down thoroughly, but of course the real interest is much more general than that. | | In accord with my experimental way, I will stick with the case of transitive inference until I have pinned it down thoroughly, but of course the real interest is much more general than that. |
| | | |
− | At first sight, the relationships seem easy enough to write out. Figure 75 shows how the various logical expressions are related to each other: The expressions <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> are conjoined in a purely syntactic fashion — much in the way that one might compile a theory from axioms without knowing what either the theory or the axioms were about — and the best way to sum up the state of information implicit in taking them together is just the expression <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}{}^{\prime\prime}</math> that would the canonical result of an equational or reversible rule of inference. From that equational inference, one might arrive at the implicational inference <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> by the most conventional implication. | + | At first sight, the relationships seem easy enough to write out. Figure 75 shows how the various logical expressions are related to each other: The expressions <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> and <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> are conjoined in a purely syntactic fashion — much in the way that one might compile a theory from axioms without knowing what either the theory or the axioms were about — and the best way to sum up the state of information implicit in taking them together is just the expression <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} q \texttt{))~(} q \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))}{}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> that would the canonical result of an equational or reversible rule of inference. From that equational inference, one might arrive at the implicational inference <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{~(} r \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> by the most conventional implication. |
| | | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| + | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o | | o-------------------o o-------------------o |
Line 2,471: |
Line 2,489: |
| Figure 75. Expressive Aspects of Transitive Inference | | Figure 75. Expressive Aspects of Transitive Inference |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| + | |} |
| | | |
| Most of the customary names for this type of process have turned out to have misleading connotations, and so I will experiment with calling it the ''expressive'' aspect of the various rules for transitive inference, simply to emphasize the fact that rules can be given for it that operate solely on signs and expressions, without necessarily needing to look at the objects that are denoted by these signs and expressions. | | Most of the customary names for this type of process have turned out to have misleading connotations, and so I will experiment with calling it the ''expressive'' aspect of the various rules for transitive inference, simply to emphasize the fact that rules can be given for it that operate solely on signs and expressions, without necessarily needing to look at the objects that are denoted by these signs and expressions. |
Line 2,481: |
Line 2,500: |
| | | |
| {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" | | {| align="center" cellpadding="8" width="90%" |
− | | The forms <math>X:Y:Z\!</math> and <math>x:y:z\!</math> are used as alternative notations for the cartesian product <math>X \times Y \times Z</math> and the tuple <math>(x, y, z),\!</math> respectively. | + | | The forms <math>X:Y:Z\!</math> and <math>x:y:z\!</math> are used as alternative notations for the cartesian product <math>X \times Y \times Z\!</math> and the tuple <math>(x, y, z),\!</math> respectively. |
| |- | | |- |
− | | In situations where we have products like <math>X:Y:Z\!</math> with <math>X = Y = Z = \mathbb{B},</math> and relations like <math>L \subseteq X:Y,</math> <math>M \subseteq X:Z,</math> <math>N \subseteq Y:Z,</math> the forms <math>L \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}:-,</math> <math>M \subseteq \mathbb{B}:-:\mathbb{B},</math> <math>N \subseteq -:\mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}</math> are used to remind us that we are considering particular ways of situating <math>L, M, N\!</math> within the product space <math>X:Y:Z.\!</math> | + | | In situations where we have products like <math>X:Y:Z\!</math> with <math>X = Y = Z = \mathbb{B},\!</math> and relations like <math>{L \subseteq X:Y},\!</math> <math>{M \subseteq X:Z},\!</math> <math>{N \subseteq Y:Z},\!</math> the forms <math>{L \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}:-},\!</math> <math>{M \subseteq \mathbb{B}:-:\mathbb{B}},\!</math> <math>{N \subseteq -:\mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}}\!</math> are used to remind us that we are considering particular ways of situating <math>{L, M, N}\!</math> within the product space <math>X:Y:Z.\!</math> |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| + | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o | | o-------------------o o-------------------o |
Line 2,550: |
Line 2,571: |
| Figure 76. Denotative Aspects of Transitive Inference | | Figure 76. Denotative Aspects of Transitive Inference |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| + | |} |
| | | |
− | A piece of syntax like <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> or <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p \Rightarrow q {}^{\prime\prime}</math> is an abstract description, and abstraction is a process that loses information about the objects described. So when we go to reverse the abstraction, as we do when we look for models of that description, there is a degree of indefiniteness that comes into play. | + | A piece of syntax like <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> or <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} p \Rightarrow q {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> is an abstract description, and abstraction is a process that loses information about the objects described. So when we go to reverse the abstraction, as we do when we look for models of that description, there is a degree of indefiniteness that comes into play. |
| | | |
− | For example, the proposition <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))}</math> is typically assigned the functional type <math>\mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B},</math> but that is only its canonical or its minimal abstract type. No sooner do we use it in a context that invokes additional variables, as we do when we next consider the proposition <math>\texttt{(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},</math> than its type is tacitly adjusted to fit the new context, for instance, acquiring the extended type <math>\mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}.</math> This is one of those things that most people eventually learn to do without blinking an eye, that is to say, unreflectively, and this is precisely what makes the same facility so much trouble to implement properly in computational form. | + | For example, the proposition <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))}\!</math> is typically assigned the functional type <math>\mathbb{B}^2 \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> but that is only its canonical or its minimal abstract type. No sooner do we use it in a context that invokes additional variables, as we do when we next consider the proposition <math>\texttt{(} q \texttt{(} r \texttt{))},\!</math> than its type is tacitly adjusted to fit the new context, for instance, acquiring the extended type <math>{\mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}}.\!</math> This is one of those things that most people eventually learn to do without blinking an eye, that is to say, unreflectively, and this is precisely what makes the same facility so much trouble to implement properly in computational form. |
| | | |
− | Both the fibering operation, that takes us from the function <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))}</math> to the relation <math>[| \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} |],</math> and the tacit extension operation, that takes us from the relation <math>[| \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}</math> to the relation <math>[| q_{207} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B},</math> have this same character of abstraction-undoing or modelling operations that require us to re-interpret the same pieces of syntax under different types. This accounts for a large part of the apparent ambiguities. | + | Both the fibering operation, that takes us from the function <math>\texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))}\!</math> to the relation <math>[| \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} |],\!</math> and the tacit extension operation, that takes us from the relation <math>[| \texttt{(} p \texttt{(} q \texttt{))} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}\!</math> to the relation <math>[| q_{207} |] \subseteq \mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B}:\mathbb{B},\!</math> have this same character of abstraction-undoing or modelling operations that require us to re-interpret the same pieces of syntax under different types. This accounts for a large part of the apparent ambiguities. |
| | | |
− | Up till now I've concentrated mostly on the abstract types of domains and propositions, things like <math>\mathbb{B}^k</math> and <math>\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B},</math> respectively. This is a little like trying to do physics all in dimensionless quantities without keeping track of the qualitative physical units. So much abstraction has its obvious limits, not to mention its hidden dangers. | + | Up till now I've concentrated mostly on the abstract types of domains and propositions, things like <math>\mathbb{B}^k\!</math> and <math>\mathbb{B}^k \to \mathbb{B},\!</math> respectively. This is a little like trying to do physics all in dimensionless quantities without keeping track of the qualitative physical units. So much abstraction has its obvious limits, not to mention its hidden dangers. |
| | | |
| To remedy this situation I will start to introduce the concrete types of domains and propositions, once again as they pertain to our current collection of examples. | | To remedy this situation I will start to introduce the concrete types of domains and propositions, once again as they pertain to our current collection of examples. |
| | | |
− | We have been using the lower case letters <math>p, q, r\!</math> for the basic propositions of abstract type <math>\mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}</math> and the upper case letters <math>P, Q, R\!</math> for the basic regions of the universe of discourse where <math>p, q, r,\!</math> respectively, hold true. | + | We have been using the lower case letters <math>p, q, r\!</math> for the basic propositions of abstract type <math>\mathbb{B}^3 \to \mathbb{B}\!</math> and the upper case letters <math>P, Q, R\!</math> for the basic regions of the universe of discourse where <math>p, q, r,\!</math> respectively, hold true. |
| | | |
− | The set of signs <math>\mathcal{X} = \{ {}^{\backprime\backprime} p {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} q {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} r {}^{\prime\prime} \}</math> is the ''alphabet'' for the universe of discourse that is notated as <math>X^\circ = [\mathcal{X}] = [p, q, r],</math> already getting sloppy about quotation marks to single out the signs. | + | The set of signs <math>\mathcal{X} = \{ {}^{\backprime\backprime} p {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} q {}^{\prime\prime}, {}^{\backprime\backprime} r {}^{\prime\prime} \}\!</math> is the ''alphabet'' for the universe of discourse that is notated as <math>X^\bullet = [\mathcal{X}] = [p, q, r],\!</math> already getting sloppy about quotation marks to single out the signs. |
| | | |
− | The universe <math>X^\circ</math> is composed of two different spaces of objects. The first is the space of positions <math>X = \langle p, q, r \rangle = \{ (p, q, r) \}.</math> The second is the space of propositions <math>X^\uparrow = (X \to \mathbb{B}).</math> | + | The universe <math>{X^\bullet}\!</math> is composed of two different spaces of objects. The first is the space of positions <math>X = \langle p, q, r \rangle = \{ (p, q, r) \}.\!</math> The second is the space of propositions <math>X^\uparrow = (X \to \mathbb{B}).\!</math> |
| | | |
| Let us make the following definitions: | | Let us make the following definitions: |
Line 2,580: |
Line 2,602: |
| |} | | |} |
| | | |
− | These are three sets of two abstract signs each, altogether staking out the qualitative dimensions of the universe of discourse <math>X^\circ</math>. | + | These are three sets of two abstract signs each, altogether staking out the qualitative dimensions of the universe of discourse <math>X^\bullet.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | Given this framework, the concrete type of the space <math>X\!</math> is <math>P^\ddagger \times Q^\ddagger \times R^\ddagger ~\cong~ \mathbb{B}^3</math> and the concrete type of each proposition in <math>X^\uparrow = (X \to \mathbb{B})</math> is <math>P^\ddagger \times Q^\ddagger \times R^\ddagger \to \mathbb{B}.</math> Given the length of the type markers, we will often omit the cartesian product symbols and write just <math>P^\ddagger Q^\ddagger R^\ddagger.</math> | + | Given this framework, the concrete type of the space <math>X\!</math> is <math>P^\ddagger \times Q^\ddagger \times R^\ddagger ~\cong~ \mathbb{B}^3\!</math> and the concrete type of each proposition in <math>X^\uparrow = (X \to \mathbb{B})\!</math> is <math>P^\ddagger \times Q^\ddagger \times R^\ddagger \to \mathbb{B}.~\!</math> Given the length of the type markers, we will often omit the cartesian product symbols and write just <math>P^\ddagger Q^\ddagger R^\ddagger.\!</math> |
| | | |
− | An abstract reference to a point of <math>X\!</math> is a triple in <math>\mathbb{B}^3.</math> A concrete reference to a point of <math>X\!</math> is a conjunction of signs from the dimensions <math>P^\ddagger, Q^\ddagger, R^\ddagger,</math> picking exactly one sign from each dimension. | + | An abstract reference to a point of <math>X\!</math> is a triple in <math>\mathbb{B}^3.\!</math> A concrete reference to a point of <math>X\!</math> is a conjunction of signs from the dimensions <math>P^\ddagger, Q^\ddagger, R^\ddagger,\!</math> picking exactly one sign from each dimension. |
| | | |
| To illustrate the use of concrete coordinates for points and concrete types for spaces and propositions, Figure 77 translates the contents of Figure 76 into the new language. | | To illustrate the use of concrete coordinates for points and concrete types for spaces and propositions, Figure 77 translates the contents of Figure 76 into the new language. |
| | | |
| + | {| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" |
| + | | |
| <pre> | | <pre> |
| o-------------------o o-------------------o | | o-------------------o o-------------------o |
Line 2,652: |
Line 2,676: |
| Figure 77. Denotative Aspects of Transitive Inference | | Figure 77. Denotative Aspects of Transitive Inference |
| </pre> | | </pre> |
| + | |} |
| | | |
| ==References== | | ==References== |
Line 2,688: |
Line 2,713: |
| {{col-break}} | | {{col-break}} |
| * [[Ampheck]] | | * [[Ampheck]] |
− | * [[Boolean algebra]]
| |
| * [[Boolean domain]] | | * [[Boolean domain]] |
| * [[Boolean function]] | | * [[Boolean function]] |
− | * [[Boolean logic]]
| |
| * [[Boolean-valued function]] | | * [[Boolean-valued function]] |
| * [[Dynamics of inquiry]] | | * [[Dynamics of inquiry]] |
− | * [[Entitative graph]]
| |
− | * [[Existential graph]]
| |
− | {{col-break}}
| |
− | * [[Graph (mathematics)|Graph]]
| |
− | * [[Graph theory]]
| |
| * [[Laws of Form]] | | * [[Laws of Form]] |
| * [[Logic of relatives]] | | * [[Logic of relatives]] |
| + | {{col-break}} |
| * [[Logic of information]] | | * [[Logic of information]] |
| * [[Logical graph]] | | * [[Logical graph]] |
Line 2,706: |
Line 2,725: |
| * [[Logical NAND]] | | * [[Logical NAND]] |
| * [[Logical NNOR]] | | * [[Logical NNOR]] |
− | {{col-break}}
| |
| * [[Minimal negation operator]] | | * [[Minimal negation operator]] |
| * [[Multigrade operator]] | | * [[Multigrade operator]] |
| + | {{col-break}} |
| * [[Parametric operator]] | | * [[Parametric operator]] |
| * [[Peirce's law]] | | * [[Peirce's law]] |
Line 2,728: |
Line 2,747: |
| ===Standard Upper Ontology (Mar–Apr 2001)=== | | ===Standard Upper Ontology (Mar–Apr 2001)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://suo.ieee.org/email/thrd187.html#04187 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20130109194711/http://suo.ieee.org/email/thrd187.html#04187 |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04187.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140423181000/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04187.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04305.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070922193822/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04305.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04413.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20071007170752/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04413.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04419.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070121063018/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04419.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04422.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04422.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04423.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070305132316/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04423.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04432.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04432.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04454.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04454.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04455.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04455.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04476.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04476.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04510.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20060718091105/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04510.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04517.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04517.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04525.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04525.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04533.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04533.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04536.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04536.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04542.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04542.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04546.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20050824231950/http://suo.ieee.org/email/msg04546.html |
| | | |
| ===Ontology List (Mar–Apr 2001)=== | | ===Ontology List (Mar–Apr 2001)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd74.html#01779 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd74.html#01779 |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg01779.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070326233418/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg01779.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg01897.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg01897.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02005.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02005.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02011.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02011.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02014.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02014.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02015.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02015.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02024.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02024.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02046.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02046.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02047.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02047.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02068.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02068.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02102.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02102.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02109.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02109.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02117.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02117.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02125.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20040116001230/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02125.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02128.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02128.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02134.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02134.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02138.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg02138.html |
| | | |
| ===Arisbe List (Feb 2003)=== | | ===Arisbe List (Feb 2003)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/thread.html#1541 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114718/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/thread.html#1541 |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001541.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114651/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001541.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001542.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114657/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001542.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001543.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115440/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001543.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001544.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114703/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001544.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001545.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115220/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001545.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001546.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115225/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001546.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001547.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114707/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001547.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001548.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114712/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001548.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001549.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115446/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001549.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001550.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114829/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001550.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001552.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115451/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001552.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001553.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115230/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001553.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001554.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115456/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001554.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001555.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114834/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001555.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001557.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115501/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001557.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001559.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115235/http://stderr.org/pipermail/arisbe/2003-February/001559.html |
| | | |
| ===Ontology List (Feb 2003)=== | | ===Ontology List (Feb 2003)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd19.html#04522 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd19.html#04522 |
− | * http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd19.html#04532 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd19.html#04532 |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04522.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04522.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04523.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070302152422/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04523.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04524.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04524.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04525.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04525.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04526.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04526.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04527.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04527.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04528.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04528.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04529.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04529.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04530.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04530.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04531.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04531.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04532.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04532.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04533.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04533.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04534.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04534.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04536.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04536.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04537.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04537.html |
− | # http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04538.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20070705085032/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04538.html |
| | | |
| ===Inquiry List (Mar 2003)=== | | ===Inquiry List (Mar 2003)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/thread.html#126 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20150224210000/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/thread.html#126 |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000126.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20150109150400/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000126.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000127.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20150109150401/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000127.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000128.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114723/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000128.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000129.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115507/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000129.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000130.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115246/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000130.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000131.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115251/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000131.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000132.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114728/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000132.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000133.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114733/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000133.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000134.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115256/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000134.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000135.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114844/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000135.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000136.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114849/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000136.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000137.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114738/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000137.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000138.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115512/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000138.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000139.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115301/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000139.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000140.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114743/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000140.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000141.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115306/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000141.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000142.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114748/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2003-March/000142.html |
| | | |
| ===NKS Forum (Apr–May 2004)=== | | ===NKS Forum (Apr–May 2004)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://forum.wolframscience.com/archive/topic/297-1.html | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20141210150520/http://forum.wolframscience.com/archive/topic/297.html |
− | * http://forum.wolframscience.com/printthread.php?threadid=297 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20130929153121/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?threadid=297&perpage=50 |
− | * http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?threadid=297
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112627/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=950#post950 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=950#post950 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112742/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=952#post952 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=952#post952 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112632/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=953#post953 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=953#post953 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112642/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=954#post954 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=954#post954 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112748/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=957#post957 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=957#post957 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112648/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=958#post958 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=958#post958 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112753/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=959#post959 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=959#post959 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112758/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=961#post961 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=961#post961 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112804/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=962#post962 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=962#post962 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112653/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=964#post964 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=964#post964 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112658/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=965#post965 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=965#post965 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112808/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=967#post967 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=967#post967 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112813/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=968#post968 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=968#post968 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112703/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=973#post973 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=973#post973 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112819/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=976#post976 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=976#post976 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112708/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=977#post977 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=977#post977 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112824/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=981#post981 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=981#post981 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112829/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=988#post988 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=988#post988 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112917/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=990#post990 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=990#post990 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112922/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=994#post994 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=994#post994 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112718/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1003#post1003 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1003#post1003 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112535/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1005#post1005 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1005#post1005 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112723/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1015#post1015 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1015#post1015 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112540/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1022#post1022 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1022#post1022 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112727/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1025#post1025 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1025#post1025 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112545/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1031#post1031 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1031#post1031 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112551/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1220#post1220 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1220#post1220 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112733/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1224#post1224 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1224#post1224 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112556/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1227#post1227 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1227#post1227 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112601/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1228#post1228 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1228#post1228 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112606/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1232#post1232 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1232#post1232 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112611/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1249#post1249 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1249#post1249 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112737/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1262#post1262 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1262#post1262 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112616/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1265#post1265 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1265#post1265 | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619112621/http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1273#post1273 |
− | # http://forum.wolframscience.com/showthread.php?postid=1273#post1273 | |
| | | |
| ===Inquiry List (2004–2006)=== | | ===Inquiry List (2004–2006)=== |
| | | |
− | * http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/thread.html#1341 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20141210145032/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/thread.html#1341 |
− | * http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/thread.html#1391 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20141207162001/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/thread.html#1391 |
− | * http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2006-January/thread.html#3364 | + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115359/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2006-January/thread.html#3364 |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001341.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20141210153038/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001341.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001342.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20141210153039/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001342.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001343.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115316/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001343.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001344.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114854/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001344.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001345.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115522/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001345.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001346.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114758/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001346.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001347.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114900/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001347.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001348.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115321/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001348.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001349.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115527/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001349.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001350.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115326/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001350.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001351.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115532/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001351.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001352.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115537/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001352.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001353.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115331/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001353.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001354.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115542/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001354.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001355.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115336/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001355.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001356.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115547/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001356.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001357.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114905/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001357.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001358.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115552/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001358.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001359.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114803/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001359.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001360.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114808/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001360.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001361.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115343/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001361.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001362.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114910/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001362.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001363.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115557/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001363.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001364.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114917/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001364.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001365.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114922/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001365.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001366.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115348/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001366.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001389.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115609/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001389.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001390.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115614/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-April/001390.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001391.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114819/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001391.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001392.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114824/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001392.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001393.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115619/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001393.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001394.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114928/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001394.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001395.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619114933/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001395.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001396.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115641/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001396.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001398.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115649/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2004-May/001398.html |
− | # http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2006-January/003364.html | + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140619115354/http://stderr.org/pipermail/inquiry/2006-January/003364.html |
| | | |
| [[Category:Artificial Intelligence]] | | [[Category:Artificial Intelligence]] |
| + | [[Category:Boolean Functions]] |
| [[Category:Charles Sanders Peirce]] | | [[Category:Charles Sanders Peirce]] |
| [[Category:Combinatorics]] | | [[Category:Combinatorics]] |
Line 2,927: |
Line 2,946: |
| [[Category:Mathematics]] | | [[Category:Mathematics]] |
| [[Category:Philosophy]] | | [[Category:Philosophy]] |
| + | [[Category:Propositional Calculus]] |
| [[Category:Semiotics]] | | [[Category:Semiotics]] |
| [[Category:Visualization]] | | [[Category:Visualization]] |