Line 649: |
Line 649: |
| | | |
| =====5.1.2.7. The Context of Interpretation===== | | =====5.1.2.7. The Context of Interpretation===== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | To the weaver's gin ye go, fair maids, |
| + | To the weaver's gin ye go, |
| + | I rede you right, gang ne'er at night, |
| + | To the weaver's gin ye go. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 306] |
| + | |
| + | As this discussion proceeds, it is designed to expand the scope of what it can analyze successfully from simple signs to complex expressions to extended texts. In this progression, the pragmatic theory of signs is used as a unifying thread to connect the different levels of complexity. Accordingly, it needs to be kept in mind throughout the discussion that references to "signs", unless specified otherwise, can generally be taken in a maximally inclusive sense, referring also to expressions and texts. |
| + | |
| + | The more complex and more extended a sign, expression, or text becomes the more occasion it has for referring to many other objects on its way to achieving its ultimate denotation. Some of these implicit, incidental, and intermediate objects can be components, properties, and relations of the sign, expression, or text itself, perhaps amounting to its accidental connotations and its intended interpretants. When it comes to a highly involved sign, expression, or text, some of its subsidiary effects and ulterior objects can even be aspects or elements of those very agents and those very media that are actually, imagined, or intended to be involved in its production, transmission, or reception. |
| + | |
| + | In many respects, these "side effects" are actually more important from a practical standpoint than the "token objects" of denotation, that is, the nominal results and the ostensible values that merely serve to mark the successful outcome of the interpretation process. Anything that an agent strives toward achieving or that a system moves toward attaining can be called its "object", and so there arises the possibility that a "global object" (GO) or a "derivative object" (DO), a thing constructed or reconstructed from various bits and pieces of extraneous references, is that which primarily or effectively calls or drives the greater action. If it strikes one as strange that an object construed from epiphenomenal marks and tangential signs should be the main motive and real object of the process of interpretation, it ought to be remembered that a special case of this already appears in the form of the semantic partitions that reconstruct the forms of their object domains. Accordingly, the types of GO's and DO's that emerge from the present considerations are just the ultimate generalizations of SEC's. |
| + | |
| + | My heart was ance as blythe and free |
| + | As simmer days were lang; |
| + | But a bonie, westlin weaver lad |
| + | Has gart me change my sang. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 306] |
| + | |
| + | Signs are typical of the contents of consciousness. Indeed, from the standpoint of the pragmatic theory of signs, where a maximally general definition of signs holds sway, signs are considered to be all inclusive, generically identical, or simply co extensive with the class of phenomena that are commonly known as the contents of consciousness. In this view of the matter, a complex expression is analogous to a complex concept, of an order that is typically but not exclusively constructed in deliberate and purposeful thinking processes, while an extended text is analogous to an ongoing stream of consciousness or a long drawn out process of reasoning, whatever its character may be. |
| + | |
| + | This analogy or identity between signs and contents of consciousness can help to explain the pains I am taking in the present discussion to elucidate the structures of self referent signs, expressions, and texts. With this key to its interpretation, a sign that denotes itself attracts interest because it presents an icon of self awareness. In other words, a sign relation that is called on to make sense of a self denoting sign affords a particular type of formal model, one that captures a relevant aspect of the structure that is involved in a content of consciousness referring to itself. In a corresponding fashion, a text that refers to itself, in whole or in part, is analogous to a conscious process that makes reference to itself, its aspects, or its instants. |
| + | |
| + | It needs to be noted what I am not saying here. I do not say that signs and texts are themselves aware, or that consciousness needs to emerge from them, however much they can serve to attract the attention of already conscious agents. Indeed, I am taking no position yet on the questions of whether or how consciousness can emerge from conceivably non conscious materials. At present, I am only interested in describing the formal relations or the structural relationships that can be noted to exist among contents of consciousness, as noted, and not to explain the bare facts of these contents, much less to explain the circumstance of consciousness itself. With regard to this purely descriptive purpose, the main task for the near future is to develop an array of conceptual frameworks that can be put to work in organizing formal descriptions and in converting suitable portions of them into effective descriptions. As long as one works under the aegis of these methodological limitations, the following maxim needs to be kept in mind: The only thing that a formal model can capture is the form of something. Whether form is of the essence in the case of the human psyche is in fact an ancient and a still important question, but not one that I hope to answer just yet. The patent answer that presents itself is to keep the question open, and to continue exploring all of the available options. |
| + | |
| + | One benefit of this openness is that it permits the exploration of the thinking mind's connection with information. |
| + | |
| + | My mither sent me to the town, |
| + | To warp a plaiden wab; |
| + | But the weary, weary warpin o't |
| + | Has gart me sigh and sab. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 307] |
| + | |
| + | The reason for my interest in signs, a reason that accounts for their part in inquiry and helps to explain their role in AIR, is that I take signs to be identical with all that is able to appear in awareness, or all that can be a content of consciousness. This amounts to saying that the ostensible analogy between signs and contents of consciousness, and thus between texts and streams of consciousness, is a potential identity. Speaking with respect to their potentiality, I would like to suggest that signs are identical with the possible contents of consciousness, and that the contents of consciousness all have the characters of potential signs. The broadest conceivable definition of what constitutes a "sign" leads to the broadest conceivable definition of what constitutes a "text", and so one is led to the idea that the whole stream of consciousness belonging to a person or a community, not just the miniscule fraction of it that happens to get written down in the conventional arrays of characters, can literally be regarded as a text. |
| + | |
| + | What appears in awareness is a case of what one calls "phenomena", and a study that considers what can be a content of consciousness is called a "phenomenology". This means that |
| + | |
| + | This is not the place to argue for the full strength of the proposed identity: |
| + | |
| + | Phenomena = Appearances in Awareness |
| + | = Contents of Consciousness |
| + | = Signs. |
| + | |
| + | Indeed, if one conceives consciousness to be a continuum, more exactly, if one considers every connected field (and stream) of consciousness to be a continuous manifold, as it very likely is, then this argument would depart from the realm of discrete signs and finite texts that is proper to computational models. |
| + | |
| + | No matter how carefully the terms are qualified, allowing the equations to apply in purely formal and wholly potential senses, the argument for the soundness of this joint identification is by no means easy, presents the danger of leading this discussion far afield, if not astray, and is, in any case, not really needed to achieve the aims of the present work. Fortunately, while the full strength of the identity is not required for the present application, it can continue to serve as a useful analogy. |
| + | |
| + | A bonie, westlin weaver lad |
| + | Sat working at his loom; |
| + | He took my heart, as wi a net, |
| + | In every knot and thrum. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 307] |
| + | |
| + | This is not the place to argue for my particular way of seeing things, whose rationale ultimately depends on the integral relationship between the pragmatic style of phenomenology and the pragmatic theory of signs. There is still too much potential for misunderstanding between the writer that is due merely to possible differences in the uses of words, and not to any matters of substance. Until these ideas can be fully developed, the relation between signs and contents of consciousness, or the relation between texts and streams of consciousness, can still be treated as a useful analogy. |
| + | |
| + | The array of what appears in awareness and the condition of what can be a content of consciousness is the range and quality of "phenomena". To study what is able to appear in awareness and to contemplate what could be a content of consciousness is to consider "phenomena" in general. A study that treats of phenomena, whether in their widest generality or restricted in a particular way, is appropriate to call a "phenomenology". There are many different styles of phenomenology, in spite of the factious pretenses of universality that are likely to be part and parcel of any style that is particular enough to find favor with a party of individual agents. |
| + | |
| + | From the pragmatic point of view, there is a close relation between phenomena and signs. |
| + | |
| + | The style of phenomenology that is needed for this work is the subject of a later discussion. Here, I make only the remarks that are needed for orientation. |
| + | |
| + | I sat beside my warpin wheel, |
| + | And ay I ca'd it roun. |
| + | But every shot and every knock, |
| + | My heart it gae a stoun. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 307] |
| + | |
| + | The pragmatic idea about phenomena is that all phenomena are signs of significant objects, except for the ones that are not. In effect, all phenomena are meant to appear before the court of significance and are deemed by their very nature to be judged as signs of potential objects. Depending on how one chooses to say it, the results of this evaluation can be rendered in one of the following ways: |
| + | |
| + | 1. Some phenomena are in fact signs of significant objects. That is, they turn out to exist in a certain relation, one that is formally identical to a sign relation, wherein they denote objects that are important to the agent in question, an agent that thereby becomes the interpreter of these signs. |
| + | |
| + | 2. Some phenomena fail to be signs of significant objects, however much they initially appear to be. In this event, the failure can be accounted for in either one of two ways: |
| + | |
| + | a. Some phenomena can fail to be signs of any objects at all. This amounts to saying that what appears is not really a sign at all, not really a sign of any object at all. |
| + | |
| + | b. All phenomena are signs in some sense, even if only granted a default, nominal, or token designation as signs, but some signs still fail to qualify as signs of significant objects, because the objects they signify are not important to the agents in question. |
| + | |
| + | The moon was sinking in the west, |
| + | Wi visage pale and wan, |
| + | As my bonie, westlin weaver lad |
| + | Convoy'd me thro the glen. |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 307] |
| + | |
| + | But what was said, or what was done, |
| + | Shame fa' me gin I tell; |
| + | But Oh! I fear the kintra soon |
| + | Will ken as weel's myself! |
| + | Robert Burns, To the Weaver's Gin You Go, [CPW, 307] |
| + | </pre> |
| | | |
| =====5.1.2.8. The Formative Tension===== | | =====5.1.2.8. The Formative Tension===== |