Changes

934 bytes removed ,  14:26, 6 November 2015
spacing in TeX <math>a \texttt{( )} = \texttt{( )},~\!</math>
Line 1: Line 1: −
<font size="3"></font> This page belongs to resource collections on [[Logic Live|Logic]] and [[Inquiry Live|Inquiry]].
+
<font size="3">&#9758;</font> This page belongs to resource collections on [[Logic Live|Logic]] and [[Inquiry Live|Inquiry]].
   −
A '''logical graph''' is a [[graph theory|graph-theoretic]] structure in one of the systems of graphical [[syntax]] that [http://mywikibiz.com/Charles_Sanders_Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce] developed for [[logic]].
+
A '''logical graph''' is a graph-theoretic structure in one of the systems of graphical syntax that Charles Sanders Peirce developed for logic.
   −
In his papers on ''[[qualitative logic]]'', ''[[entitative graph]]s'', and ''[[existential graph]]s'', Peirce developed several versions of a graphical formalism, or a graph-theoretic formal language, designed to be interpreted for logic.
+
In his papers on ''qualitative logic'', ''entitative graphs'', and ''existential graphs'', Peirce developed several versions of a graphical formalism, or a graph-theoretic formal language, designed to be interpreted for logic.
    
In the century since Peirce initiated this line of development, a variety of formal systems have branched out from what is abstractly the same formal base of graph-theoretic structures.  This article examines the common basis of these formal systems from a bird's eye view, focusing on those aspects of form that are shared by the entire family of algebras, calculi, or languages, however they happen to be viewed in a given application.
 
In the century since Peirce initiated this line of development, a variety of formal systems have branched out from what is abstractly the same formal base of graph-theoretic structures.  This article examines the common basis of these formal systems from a bird's eye view, focusing on those aspects of form that are shared by the entire family of algebras, calculi, or languages, however they happen to be viewed in a given application.
      
==Abstract point of view==
 
==Abstract point of view==
    
{| width="100%" cellpadding="2" cellspacing="0"
 
{| width="100%" cellpadding="2" cellspacing="0"
| width="60%" |
+
| width="60%" | &nbsp;
| width="40%" | ''Wollust ward dem Wurm gegeben ''
+
| width="40%" | ''Wollust ward dem Wurm gegeben &hellip;''
 
|-
 
|-
|
+
| &nbsp;
 
| align="right" | &mdash; Friedrich Schiller, ''An die Freude''
 
| align="right" | &mdash; Friedrich Schiller, ''An die Freude''
 
|}
 
|}
   −
The bird's eye view in question is more formally known as the perspective of formal equivalence, from which remove one cannot see many distinctions that appear momentous from lower levels of abstraction.  In particular, expressions of different formalisms whose syntactic structures are [[isomorphic]] from the standpoint of [[algebra]] or [[topology]] are not recognized as being different from each other in any significant sense.  Though we may note in passing such historical details as the circumstance that Charles Sanders Peirce used a ''streamer-cross symbol'' where [[George Spencer Brown]] used a ''carpenter's square marker'', the theme of principal interest at the abstract level of form is neutral with regard to variations of that order.
+
The bird's eye view in question is more formally known as the perspective of formal equivalence, from which remove one cannot see many distinctions that appear momentous from lower levels of abstraction.  In particular, expressions of different formalisms whose syntactic structures are isomorphic from the standpoint of algebra or topology are not recognized as being different from each other in any significant sense.  Though we may note in passing such historical details as the circumstance that Charles Sanders Peirce used a ''streamer-cross symbol'' where George Spencer Brown used a ''carpenter's square marker'', the theme of principal interest at the abstract level of form is neutral with regard to variations of that order.
    
==In lieu of a beginning==
 
==In lieu of a beginning==
   −
Consider the formal equations indicated in Figures 1 and 2.
+
Consider the formal equations indicated in Figures&nbsp;1 and 2.
    
{| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0"
 
{| align="center" border="0" cellpadding="10" cellspacing="0"
Line 30: Line 29:  
|}
 
|}
   −
For the time being these two forms of transformation may be referred to as ''[[axioms]]'' or ''initial equations''.
+
For the time being these two forms of transformation may be referred to as ''axioms'' or ''initial equations''.
    
==Duality : logical and topological==
 
==Duality : logical and topological==
Line 36: Line 35:  
There are two types of duality that have to be kept separately mind in the use of logical graphs &mdash; logical duality and topological duality.
 
There are two types of duality that have to be kept separately mind in the use of logical graphs &mdash; logical duality and topological duality.
   −
There is a standard way that graphs of the order that Peirce considered, those embedded in a continuous [[manifold]] like that commonly represented by a plane sheet of paper &mdash; with or without the paper bridges that Peirce used to augment its topological genus &mdash; can be represented in linear text as what are called ''parse strings'' or ''traversal strings'' and parsed into ''pointer structures'' in computer memory.
+
There is a standard way that graphs of the order that Peirce considered, those embedded in a continuous manifold like that commonly represented by a plane sheet of paper &mdash; with or without the paper bridges that Peirce used to augment its topological genus &mdash; can be represented in linear text as what are called ''parse strings'' or ''traversal strings'' and parsed into ''pointer structures'' in computer memory.
    
A blank sheet of paper can be represented in linear text as a blank space, but that way of doing it tends to be confusing unless the logical expression under consideration is set off in a separate display.
 
A blank sheet of paper can be represented in linear text as a blank space, but that way of doing it tends to be confusing unless the logical expression under consideration is set off in a separate display.
Line 46: Line 45:  
|}
 
|}
   −
This can be written inline as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(~(~)~)} = \quad {}^{\prime\prime}</math> or set off in a text display as follows:
+
This can be written inline as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{( ( ) )} = \quad {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> or set off in a text display as follows:
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
| width="33%" | <math>\texttt{(~(~)~)}</math>
+
| width="33%" | <math>\texttt{( ( ) )}\!</math>
 
| width="34%" | <math>=\!</math>
 
| width="34%" | <math>=\!</math>
| width="33%" |
+
| width="33%" | &nbsp;
 
|}
 
|}
   −
When we turn to representing the corresponding expressions in computer memory, where they can be manipulated with utmost facility, we begin by transforming the planar graphs into their topological duals.  The planar regions of the original graph correspond to nodes (or points) of the [[dual graph]], and the boundaries between planar regions in the original graph correspond to edges (or lines) between the nodes of the dual graph.
+
When we turn to representing the corresponding expressions in computer memory, where they can be manipulated with utmost facility, we begin by transforming the planar graphs into their topological duals.  The planar regions of the original graph correspond to nodes (or points) of the dual graph, and the boundaries between planar regions in the original graph correspond to edges (or lines) between the nodes of the dual graph.
    
For example, overlaying the corresponding dual graphs on the plane-embedded graphs shown above, we get the following composite picture:
 
For example, overlaying the corresponding dual graphs on the plane-embedded graphs shown above, we get the following composite picture:
Line 62: Line 61:  
|}
 
|}
   −
Though it's not really there in the most abstract topology of the matter, for all sorts of pragmatic reasons we find ourselves compelled to single out the outermost region of the plane in a distinctive way and to mark it as the ''[[root node]]'' of the corresponding dual graph.  In the present style of Figure the root nodes are marked by horizontal strike-throughs.
+
Though it's not really there in the most abstract topology of the matter, for all sorts of pragmatic reasons we find ourselves compelled to single out the outermost region of the plane in a distinctive way and to mark it as the ''root node'' of the corresponding dual graph.  In the present style of Figure the root nodes are marked by horizontal strike-throughs.
    
Extracting the dual graphs from their composite matrices, we get this picture:
 
Extracting the dual graphs from their composite matrices, we get this picture:
Line 70: Line 69:  
|}
 
|}
   −
It is easy to see the relationship between the parenthetical expressions of Peirce's logical graphs, that somewhat clippedly picture the ordered containments of their formal contents, and the associated dual graphs, that constitute the species of [[rooted tree]]s here to be described.
+
It is easy to see the relationship between the parenthetical expressions of Peirce's logical graphs, that somewhat clippedly picture the ordered containments of their formal contents, and the associated dual graphs, that constitute the species of rooted trees here to be described.
   −
In the case of our last example, a moment's contemplation of the following picture will lead us to see that we can get the corresponding parenthesis string by starting at the root of the tree, climbing up the left side of the tree until we reach the top, then climbing back down the right side of the tree until we return to the root, all the while reading off the symbols, in this case either <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} {}^{\prime\prime}</math> or <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{)} {}^{\prime\prime},</math> that we happen to encounter in our travels.
+
In the case of our last example, a moment's contemplation of the following picture will lead us to see that we can get the corresponding parenthesis string by starting at the root of the tree, climbing up the left side of the tree until we reach the top, then climbing back down the right side of the tree until we return to the root, all the while reading off the symbols, in this case either <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(} {}^{\prime\prime}\!</math> or <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{)} {}^{\prime\prime},\!</math> that we happen to encounter in our travels.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 78: Line 77:  
|}
 
|}
   −
This ritual is called ''[[traversing]]'' the tree, and the string read off is called the ''[[traversal string]]'' of the tree.  The reverse ritual, that passes from the string to the tree, is called ''[[parsing]]'' the string, and the tree constructed is called the ''[[parse graph]]'' of the string.  The speakers thereof tend to be a bit loose in this language, often using ''[[parse string]]'' to mean the string that gets parsed into the associated graph.
+
This ritual is called ''traversing'' the tree, and the string read off is called the ''traversal string'' of the tree.  The reverse ritual, that passes from the string to the tree, is called ''parsing'' the string, and the tree constructed is called the ''parse graph'' of the string.  The speakers thereof tend to be a bit loose in this language, often using ''parse string'' to mean the string that gets parsed into the associated graph.
   −
We have treated in some detail various forms of the initial equation or logical axiom that is formulated in string form as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(~(~)~)} = \quad {}^{\prime\prime}.</math>  For the sake of comparison, let's record the plane-embedded and topological dual forms of the axiom that is formulated in string form as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{(~)(~)} = \texttt{(~)} {}^{\prime\prime}.</math>
+
We have treated in some detail various forms of the initial equation or logical axiom that is formulated in string form as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{( ( ) )} = \quad {}^{\prime\prime}.~\!</math>  For the sake of comparison, let's record the plane-embedded and topological dual forms of the axiom that is formulated in string form as <math>{}^{\backprime\backprime} \texttt{( )( )} = \texttt{( )} {}^{\prime\prime}.\!</math>
    
First the plane-embedded maps:
 
First the plane-embedded maps:
Line 106: Line 105:  
|}
 
|}
   −
We have at this point enough material to begin thinking about the forms of [[analogy]], [[iconicity]], [[metaphor]], [[morphism]], whatever you want to call them, that are pertinent to the use of logical graphs in their various logical interpretations, for instance, those that Peirce described as ''[[entitative graph]]s'' and ''[[existential graph]]s''.
+
We have at this point enough material to begin thinking about the forms of analogy, iconicity, metaphor, morphism, whatever you want to call them, that are pertinent to the use of logical graphs in their various logical interpretations, for instance, those that Peirce described as ''entitative graphs'' and ''existential graphs''.
    
==Computational representation==
 
==Computational representation==
Line 148: Line 147:  
Though it may not seem too exciting, logically speaking, there are many reasons to make oneself at home with the system of forms that is represented indifferently, topologically speaking, by rooted trees, balanced strings of parentheses, or finite sets of non-intersecting simple closed curves in the plane.
 
Though it may not seem too exciting, logically speaking, there are many reasons to make oneself at home with the system of forms that is represented indifferently, topologically speaking, by rooted trees, balanced strings of parentheses, or finite sets of non-intersecting simple closed curves in the plane.
   −
:* One reason is that it gives us a respectable example of a sign domain on which to cut our semiotic teeth, non-trivial in the sense that it contains a [[countable]] [[infinity]] of signs.
+
:* One reason is that it gives us a respectable example of a sign domain on which to cut our semiotic teeth, non-trivial in the sense that it contains a countable infinity of signs.
   −
:* Another reason is that it allows us to study a simple form of [[computation]] that is recognizable as a species of ''[[semiosis]]'', or sign-transforming process.
+
:* Another reason is that it allows us to study a simple form of computation that is recognizable as a species of ''[[semiosis]]'', or sign-transforming process.
   −
This space of forms, along with the two axioms that induce its [[partition of a set|partition]] into exactly two [[equivalence class]]es, is what [[George Spencer Brown]] called the ''primary arithmetic''.
+
This space of forms, along with the two axioms that induce its partition into exactly two equivalence classes, is what George Spencer Brown called the ''primary arithmetic''.
    
The axioms of the primary arithmetic are shown below, as they appear in both graph and string forms, along with pairs of names that come in handy for referring to the two opposing directions of applying the axioms.
 
The axioms of the primary arithmetic are shown below, as they appear in both graph and string forms, along with pairs of names that come in handy for referring to the two opposing directions of applying the axioms.
Line 171: Line 170:  
| <math>S_0\!</math>
 
| <math>S_0\!</math>
 
| <math>=\!</math>
 
| <math>=\!</math>
| <math>\{ \ominus, \vert \} = \{</math>[[Image:Rooted Node.jpg|16px]], [[Image:Rooted Edge.jpg|12px]]<math>\}\!</math>
+
| <math>\{ \ominus, \vert \} = \{\!</math>[[Image:Rooted Node.jpg|16px]], [[Image:Rooted Edge.jpg|12px]]<math>\}\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
   −
Simple intuition, or a simple inductive proof, assures us that any rooted tree can be reduced by way of the arithmetic initials either to a root node [[Image:Rooted Node.jpg|16px]] or else to a rooted edge [[Image:Rooted Edge.jpg|12px]] .
+
Simple intuition, or a simple inductive proof, assures us that any rooted tree can be reduced by way of the arithmetic initials either to a root node [[Image:Rooted Node.jpg|16px]] or else to a rooted edge [[Image:Rooted Edge.jpg|12px]]&nbsp;.
    
For example, consider the reduction that proceeds as follows:
 
For example, consider the reduction that proceeds as follows:
Line 182: Line 181:  
|}
 
|}
   −
Regarded as a semiotic process, this amounts to a sequence of signs, every one after the first serving as the ''[[interpretant]]'' of its predecessor, ending in a final sign that may be taken as the canonical sign for their common object, in the upshot being the result of the computation process.  Simple as it is, this exhibits the main features of any computation, namely, a semiotic process that proceeds from an obscure sign to a clear sign of the same object, being in its aim and effect an action on behalf of clarification.
+
Regarded as a semiotic process, this amounts to a sequence of signs, every one after the first serving as the ''interpretant'' of its predecessor, ending in a final sign that may be taken as the canonical sign for their common object, in the upshot being the result of the computation process.  Simple as it is, this exhibits the main features of any computation, namely, a semiotic process that proceeds from an obscure sign to a clear sign of the same object, being in its aim and effect an action on behalf of clarification.
    
===Primary algebra as pattern calculus===
 
===Primary algebra as pattern calculus===
   −
Experience teaches that complex objects are best approached in a gradual, laminar, [[module|modular]] fashion, one step, one layer, one piece at a time, and it's just as much the case when the complexity of the object is irreducible, that is, when the articulations of the representation are necessarily at joints that are cloven disjointedly from nature, with some assembly required in the synthetic integrity of the intuition.
+
Experience teaches that complex objects are best approached in a gradual, laminar, modular fashion, one step, one layer, one piece at a time, and it's just as much the case when the complexity of the object is irreducible, that is, when the articulations of the representation are necessarily at joints that are cloven disjointedly from nature, with some assembly required in the synthetic integrity of the intuition.
    
That's one good reason for spending so much time on the first half of [[zeroth order logic]], represented here by the primary arithmetic, a level of formal structure that C.S. Peirce verged on intuiting at numerous points and times in his work on logical graphs, and that Spencer Brown named and brought more completely to life.
 
That's one good reason for spending so much time on the first half of [[zeroth order logic]], represented here by the primary arithmetic, a level of formal structure that C.S. Peirce verged on intuiting at numerous points and times in his work on logical graphs, and that Spencer Brown named and brought more completely to life.
   −
There is one other reason for lingering a while longer in these primitive forests, and this is that an acquaintance with "bare trees", those as yet unadorned with literal or numerical labels, will provide a firm basis for understanding what's really at issue in such problems as the "ontological status of variables".
+
There is one other reason for lingering a while longer in these primitive forests, and this is that an acquaintance with &ldquo;bare trees&rdquo;, those as yet unadorned with literal or numerical labels, will provide a firm basis for understanding what's really at issue in such problems as the &ldquo;ontological status of variables&rdquo;.
   −
It is probably best to illustrate this theme in the setting of a concrete case, which we can do by reviewing the previous example of reductive evaluation shown in Figure 16.
+
It is probably best to illustrate this theme in the setting of a concrete case, which we can do by reviewing the previous example of reductive evaluation shown in Figure&nbsp;16.
   −
The observation of several ''semioses'', or sign-transformations, of roughly this shape will most likely lead an observer with any observational facility whatever to notice that it doesn't really matter what sorts of branches happen to sprout from the side of the root aside from the lone edge that also grows there the end result will always be the same.
+
The observation of several ''semioses'', or sign-transformations, of roughly this shape will most likely lead an observer with any observational facility whatever to notice that it doesn't really matter what sorts of branches happen to sprout from the side of the root aside from the lone edge that also grows there &mdash; the end result will always be the same.
    
Our observer might think to summarize the results of many such observations by introducing a label or variable to signify any shape of branch whatever, writing something like the following:
 
Our observer might think to summarize the results of many such observations by introducing a label or variable to signify any shape of branch whatever, writing something like the following:
Line 204: Line 203:  
Observations like that, made about an arithmetic of any variety, germinated by their summarizations, are the root of all algebra.
 
Observations like that, made about an arithmetic of any variety, germinated by their summarizations, are the root of all algebra.
   −
Speaking of algebra, and having encountered already one example of an algebraic law, we might as well introduce the axioms of the ''primary algebra'', once again deriving their substance and their name from the works of [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] and [[George Spencer Brown]], respectively.
+
Speaking of algebra, and having encountered already one example of an algebraic law, we might as well introduce the axioms of the ''primary algebra'', once again deriving their substance and their name from the works of Charles Sanders Peirce and George Spencer Brown, respectively.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 212: Line 211:  
|}
 
|}
   −
The choice of axioms for any formal system is to some degree a matter of aesthetics, as it is commonly the case that many different selections of formal rules will serve as axioms to derive all the rest as theorems.  As it happens, the example of an algebraic law that we noticed first, <math>a(~) = (~),</math> as simple as it appears, proves to be provable as a theorem on the grounds of the foregoing axioms.
+
The choice of axioms for any formal system is to some degree a matter of aesthetics, as it is commonly the case that many different selections of formal rules will serve as axioms to derive all the rest as theorems.  As it happens, the example of an algebraic law that we noticed first, <math>a \texttt{( )} = \texttt{( )},~\!</math> as simple as it appears, proves to be provable as a theorem on the grounds of the foregoing axioms.
    
We might also notice at this point a subtle difference between the primary arithmetic and the primary algebra with respect to the grounds of justification that we have naturally if tacitly adopted for their respective sets of axioms.
 
We might also notice at this point a subtle difference between the primary arithmetic and the primary algebra with respect to the grounds of justification that we have naturally if tacitly adopted for their respective sets of axioms.
   −
The arithmetic axioms were introduced by fiat, in a quasi-[[apriori]] fashion, though of course it is only long prior experience with the practical uses of comparably developed generations of formal systems that would actually induce us to such a quasi-primal move.  The algebraic axioms, in contrast, can be seen to derive their motive and their justice from the observation and summarization of patterns that are visible in the arithmetic spectrum.
+
The arithmetic axioms were introduced by fiat, in an ''a&nbsp;priori'' fashion, though of course it is only long prior experience with the practical uses of comparably developed generations of formal systems that would actually induce us to such a quasi-primal move.  The algebraic axioms, in contrast, can be seen to derive their motive and their justice from the observation and summarization of patterns that are visible in the arithmetic spectrum.
    
==Formal development==
 
==Formal development==
Line 278: Line 277:  
|}
 
|}
   −
All of the axioms in this set have the form of equations.  This means that all of the inference steps that they allow are reversible.  The proof annotation scheme employed below makes use of a double bar <math>\overline{\underline{~~~~~~}}</math> to mark this fact, although it will often be left to the reader to decide which of the two possible directions is the one required for applying the indicated axiom.
+
All of the axioms in this set have the form of equations.  This means that all of the inference steps that they allow are reversible.  The proof annotation scheme employed below makes use of a double bar <math>=\!=\!=\!=\!=\!=</math> to mark this fact, although it will often be left to the reader to decide which of the two possible directions is the one required for applying the indicated axiom.
    
===Frequently used theorems===
 
===Frequently used theorems===
Line 290: Line 289:  
====C<sub>1</sub>. Double negation====
 
====C<sub>1</sub>. Double negation====
   −
The first theorem goes under the names of ''Consequence 1'' <math>(C_1)\!</math>, the ''double negation theorem'' (DNT), or ''Reflection''.
+
The first theorem goes under the names of ''Consequence&nbsp;1'' <math>(C_1)\!</math>, the ''double negation theorem'' (DNT), or ''Reflection''.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 296: Line 295:  
|}
 
|}
   −
The proof that follows is adapted from the one that was given by [[George Spencer Brown]] in his book ''Laws of Form'' (LOF) and credited to two of his students, John Dawes and D.A. Utting.
+
The proof that follows is adapted from the one that was given by George Spencer Brown in his book ''Laws of Form'' (LOF) and credited to two of his students, John Dawes and D.A. Utting.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="8"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="8"
Line 356: Line 355:  
====C<sub>2</sub>. Generation theorem====
 
====C<sub>2</sub>. Generation theorem====
   −
One theorem of frequent use goes under the nickname of the ''weed and seed theorem'' (WAST).  The proof is just an exercise in mathematical induction, once a suitable basis is laid down, and it will be left as an exercise for the reader.  What the WAST says is that a label can be freely distributed or freely erased anywhere in a subtree whose root is labeled with that label.  The second in our list of frequently used theorems is in fact the base case of this weed and seed theorem.  In LOF, it goes by the names of ''Consequence 2'' <math>(C_2)\!</math> or ''Generation''.
+
One theorem of frequent use goes under the nickname of the ''weed and seed theorem'' (WAST).  The proof is just an exercise in mathematical induction, once a suitable basis is laid down, and it will be left as an exercise for the reader.  What the WAST says is that a label can be freely distributed or freely erased anywhere in a subtree whose root is labeled with that label.  The second in our list of frequently used theorems is in fact the base case of this weed and seed theorem.  In LOF, it goes by the names of ''Consequence&nbsp;2'' <math>(C_2)\!</math> or ''Generation''.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 410: Line 409:  
====C<sub>3</sub>. Dominant form theorem====
 
====C<sub>3</sub>. Dominant form theorem====
   −
The third of the frequently used theorems of service to this survey is one that Spencer-Brown annotates as ''Consequence 3'' <math>(C_3)\!</math> or ''Integration''.  A better mnemonic might be ''dominance and recession theorem'' (DART), but perhaps the brevity of ''dominant form theorem'' (DFT) is sufficient reminder of its double-edged role in proofs.
+
The third of the frequently used theorems of service to this survey is one that Spencer-Brown annotates as ''Consequence&nbsp;3'' <math>(C_3)\!</math> or ''Integration''.  A better mnemonic might be ''dominance and recession theorem'' (DART), but perhaps the brevity of ''dominant form theorem'' (DFT) is sufficient reminder of its double-edged role in proofs.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 461: Line 460:     
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
| <math>((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Rightarrow p</math>
+
| <math>((p \Rightarrow q) \Rightarrow p) \Rightarrow p\!</math>
 
|}
 
|}
   −
The existential graph representation of Peirce's law is shown in Figure 33.
+
The existential graph representation of Peirce's law is shown in Figure&nbsp;33.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="10"
Line 470: Line 469:  
|}
 
|}
   −
A graphical proof of Peirce's law is shown in Figure 34.
+
A graphical proof of Peirce's law is shown in Figure&nbsp;34.
    
{| align="center" cellpadding="8"
 
{| align="center" cellpadding="8"
Line 518: Line 517:  
====Praeclarum theorema====
 
====Praeclarum theorema====
   −
An illustrious example of a propositional theorem is the ''praeclarum theorema'', the ''admirable'', ''shining'', or ''splendid'' theorem of [[Leibniz]].
+
An illustrious example of a propositional theorem is the ''praeclarum theorema'', the ''admirable'', ''shining'', or ''splendid'' theorem of Leibniz.
    
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
 
{| align="center" cellspacing="6" width="90%" <!--QUOTE-->
Line 604: Line 603:  
a b + a c + b c
 
a b + a c + b c
 
\end{matrix}</math>
 
\end{matrix}</math>
|
+
| &nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;&nbsp;
 
|}
 
|}
   Line 667: Line 666:  
==Bibliography==
 
==Bibliography==
   −
* [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz, G.W.]] (1679–1686 ?), "Addenda to the Specimen of the Universal Calculus", pp. 40–46 in G.H.R. Parkinson (ed. and trans., 1966), ''Leibniz : Logical Papers'', Oxford University Press, London, UK.
+
* Leibniz, G.W. (1679&ndash;1686 ?), &ldquo;Addenda to the Specimen of the Universal Calculus&rdquo;, pp. 40&ndash;46 in G.H.R. Parkinson (ed. and trans., 1966), ''Leibniz : Logical Papers'', Oxford University Press, London, UK.
 
  −
* [[Charles Peirce (Bibliography)|Peirce, C.S., Bibliography]].
     −
* [[Charles Peirce|Peirce, C.S.]] (1931–1935, 1958), ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', vols. 1–6, [[Charles Hartshorne]] and [[Paul Weiss]] (eds.), vols. 7–8, [[Arthur W. Burks]] (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.  Cited as (CP volume.paragraph).
+
* Peirce, C.S. (1931&ndash;1935, 1958), ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', vols. 1&ndash;6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vols. 7&ndash;8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.  Cited as (CP&nbsp;volume.paragraph).
   −
* Peirce, C.S. (1981–), ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition'', [[Peirce Edition Project]] (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianopolis, IN.  Cited as (CE volume, page).
+
* Peirce, C.S. (1981&ndash;), ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN.  Cited as (CE&nbsp;volume, page).
   −
* Peirce, C.S. (1885), "On the Algebra of Logic : A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation", ''American Journal of Mathematics'' 7 (1885), 180–202.  Reprinted as CP 3.359–403 and CE 5, 162–190.
+
* Peirce, C.S. (1885), &ldquo;On the Algebra of Logic : A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation&rdquo;, ''American Journal of Mathematics'' 7 (1885), 180&ndash;202.  Reprinted as CP&nbsp;3.359&ndash;403 and CE&nbsp;5, 162&ndash;190.
   −
* Peirce, C.S. (''c.'' 1886), "Qualitative Logic", MS 736.  Published as pp. 101–115 in Carolyn Eisele (ed., 1976), ''The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce, Volume 4, Mathematical Philosophy'', Mouton, The Hague.
+
* Peirce, C.S. (''c.'' 1886), &ldquo;Qualitative Logic&rdquo;, MS 736.  Published as pp. 101&ndash;115 in Carolyn Eisele (ed., 1976), ''The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce, Volume 4, Mathematical Philosophy'', Mouton, The Hague.
   −
* Peirce, C.S. (1886 a), "Qualitative Logic", MS 582.  Published as pp. 323–371 in ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Volume 5, 1884–1886'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1993.
+
* Peirce, C.S. (1886 a), &ldquo;Qualitative Logic&rdquo;, MS 582.  Published as pp. 323&ndash;371 in ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Volume 5, 1884&ndash;1886'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1993.
   −
* Peirce, C.S. (1886 b), "The Logic of Relatives : Qualitative and Quantitative", MS 584.  Published as pp. 372–378 in ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Volume 5, 1884–1886'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1993.
+
* Peirce, C.S. (1886 b), &ldquo;The Logic of Relatives : Qualitative and Quantitative&rdquo;, MS 584.  Published as pp. 372&ndash;378 in ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce : A Chronological Edition, Volume 5, 1884&ndash;1886'', Peirce Edition Project (eds.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1993.
   −
* [[George Spencer Brown|Spencer Brown, George]] (1969), ''[[Laws of Form]]'', George Allen and Unwin, London, UK.
+
* Spencer Brown, George (1969), ''Laws of Form'', George Allen and Unwin, London, UK.
    
==Resources==
 
==Resources==
    
* [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
 
* [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
** [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/LogicalGraph.html Logical Graph : Introduction]
+
** [http://planetmath.org/LogicalGraphIntroduction Logical Graph : Introduction]
** [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/LogicalGraphFormalDevelopment.html Logical Graph : Formal Development]
+
** [http://planetmath.org/LogicalGraphFormalDevelopment Logical Graph : Formal Development]
    
* Bergman and Paavola (eds.), [http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.html Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms]
 
* Bergman and Paavola (eds.), [http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.html Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms]
Line 697: Line 694:  
* [http://dr-dau.net/index.shtml Dau, Frithjof]
 
* [http://dr-dau.net/index.shtml Dau, Frithjof]
 
** [http://dr-dau.net/eg_readings.shtml Peirce's Existential Graphs : Readings and Links]
 
** [http://dr-dau.net/eg_readings.shtml Peirce's Existential Graphs : Readings and Links]
** [http://dr-dau.net/pc.shtml Existential Graphs as Moving Pictures of Thought] Computer Animated Proof of Leibniz's Praeclarum Theorema
+
** [http://web.archive.org/web/20070706192257/http://dr-dau.net/pc.shtml Existential Graphs as Moving Pictures of Thought] &mdash; Computer Animated Proof of Leibniz's Praeclarum Theorema
    
* [http://www.math.uic.edu/~kauffman/ Kauffman, Louis H.]
 
* [http://www.math.uic.edu/~kauffman/ Kauffman, Louis H.]
Line 716: Line 713:  
===Focal nodes===
 
===Focal nodes===
   −
{{col-begin}}
  −
{{col-break}}
   
* [[Inquiry Live]]
 
* [[Inquiry Live]]
{{col-break}}
   
* [[Logic Live]]
 
* [[Logic Live]]
{{col-end}}
      
===Peer nodes===
 
===Peer nodes===
   −
{{col-begin}}
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ InterSciWiki]
{{col-break}}
   
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ MyWikiBiz]
 
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ MyWikiBiz]
* [http://mathweb.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ MathWeb Wiki]
+
* [http://ref.subwiki.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ Subject Wikis]
* [http://netknowledge.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ NetKnowledge]
+
* [http://en.wikiversity.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ Wikiversity]
{{col-break}}
+
* [http://beta.wikiversity.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ Wikiversity Beta]
* [http://wiki.oercommons.org/mediawiki/index.php/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ OER Commons]
  −
* [http://p2pfoundation.net/Logical_Graph Logical Graph @ P2P Foundation]
  −
* [http://semanticweb.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph @ SemanticWeb]
  −
{{col-end}}
      
===Logical operators===
 
===Logical operators===
Line 813: Line 801:  
===Related articles===
 
===Related articles===
   −
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Semiotic_Information Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Semiotic Information&rdquo;]
+
{{col-begin}}
 
+
{{col-break}}
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Introduction_to_Inquiry_Driven_Systems Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Introduction To Inquiry Driven Systems&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Cactus_Language Cactus Language]
 
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Futures_Of_Logical_Graphs Futures Of Logical Graphs]
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Essays/Prospects_For_Inquiry_Driven_Systems Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Prospects For Inquiry Driven Systems&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Propositional_Equation_Reasoning_Systems Propositional Equation Reasoning Systems]
 
+
{{col-break}}
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Inquiry_Driven_Systems Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Inquiry Driven Systems : Inquiry Into Inquiry&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Differential_Logic_:_Introduction Differential Logic : Introduction]
 
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Differential_Propositional_Calculus Differential Propositional Calculus]
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Propositional_Equation_Reasoning_Systems Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Propositional Equation Reasoning Systems&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Differential_Logic_and_Dynamic_Systems_2.0 Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems]
 
+
{{col-break}}
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Differential_Logic_:_Introduction Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Differential Logic : Introduction&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Prospects_for_Inquiry_Driven_Systems Prospects for Inquiry Driven Systems]
 
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Introduction_to_Inquiry_Driven_Systems Introduction to Inquiry Driven Systems]
* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/DifferentialPropositionalCalculus.html Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Differential Propositional Calculus&rdquo;]
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Inquiry_Driven_Systems Inquiry Driven Systems : Inquiry Into Inquiry]
 
+
{{col-end}}
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Directory:Jon_Awbrey/Papers/Differential_Logic_and_Dynamic_Systems_2.0 Jon Awbrey, &ldquo;Differential Logic and Dynamic Systems&rdquo;]
      
==Document history==
 
==Document history==
Line 833: Line 820:  
Portions of the above article were adapted from the following sources under the [[GNU Free Documentation License]], under other applicable licenses, or by permission of the copyright holders.
 
Portions of the above article were adapted from the following sources under the [[GNU Free Documentation License]], under other applicable licenses, or by permission of the copyright holders.
   −
{{col-begin}}
+
* [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/wiki/index.php/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://intersci.ss.uci.edu/ InterSciWiki]
{{col-break}}
   
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://mywikibiz.com/ MyWikiBiz]
 
* [http://mywikibiz.com/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://mywikibiz.com/ MyWikiBiz]
* [http://mathweb.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://mathweb.org/wiki/ MathWeb Wiki]
+
* [http://planetmath.org/LogicalGraphIntroduction Logical Graph 1], [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
* [http://netknowledge.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://netknowledge.org/ NetKnowledge]
+
* [http://planetmath.org/LogicalGraphFormalDevelopment Logical Graph 2], [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
* [http://p2pfoundation.net/Logical_Graph Logical Graph], [http://p2pfoundation.net/ P2P Foundation]
   
* [http://semanticweb.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://semanticweb.org/ Semantic Web]
 
* [http://semanticweb.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://semanticweb.org/ Semantic Web]
{{col-break}}
+
* [http://wikinfo.org/w/index.php/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://wikinfo.org/w/ Wikinfo]
* [http://proofwiki.org/wiki/Definition:Logical_Graph Logical Graph], [http://proofwiki.org/ ProofWiki]
+
* [http://en.wikiversity.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://en.wikiversity.org/ Wikiversity]
* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/LogicalGraph.html Logical Graph : 1], [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
  −
* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/LogicalGraphFormalDevelopment.html Logical Graph : 2], [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath]
  −
* [http://knol.google.com/k/logical-graphs-1 Logical Graph : 1], [http://knol.google.com/ Google Knol]
  −
* [http://knol.google.com/k/logical-graphs-2 Logical Graph : 2], [http://knol.google.com/ Google Knol]
  −
{{col-break}}
   
* [http://beta.wikiversity.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://beta.wikiversity.org/ Wikiversity Beta]
 
* [http://beta.wikiversity.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://beta.wikiversity.org/ Wikiversity Beta]
* [http://getwiki.net/-Logical_Graph Logical Graph], [http://getwiki.net/ GetWiki]
+
* [http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Logical_graph&oldid=67277491 Logical Graph], [http://en.wikipedia.org/ Wikipedia]
* [http://wikinfo.org/index.php/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://wikinfo.org/ Wikinfo]
  −
* [http://textop.org/wiki/index.php?title=Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://textop.org/wiki/ Textop Wiki]
  −
* [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Logical_graph Logical Graph], [http://en.wikipedia.org/ Wikipedia]
  −
{{col-end}}
  −
 
  −
<br><sharethis />
     −
[[Category:Inquiry]]
  −
[[Category:Open Educational Resource]]
  −
[[Category:Peer Educational Resource]]
   
[[Category:Artificial Intelligence]]
 
[[Category:Artificial Intelligence]]
 +
[[Category:Boolean Functions]]
 +
[[Category:Charles Sanders Peirce]]
 
[[Category:Combinatorics]]
 
[[Category:Combinatorics]]
 
[[Category:Computer Science]]
 
[[Category:Computer Science]]
Line 866: Line 839:  
[[Category:Formal Languages]]
 
[[Category:Formal Languages]]
 
[[Category:Formal Systems]]
 
[[Category:Formal Systems]]
 +
[[Category:George Spencer Brown]]
 
[[Category:Graph Theory]]
 
[[Category:Graph Theory]]
 
[[Category:History of Logic]]
 
[[Category:History of Logic]]
 
[[Category:History of Mathematics]]
 
[[Category:History of Mathematics]]
 +
[[Category:Inquiry]]
 
[[Category:Knowledge Representation]]
 
[[Category:Knowledge Representation]]
 +
[[Category:Laws of Form]]
 
[[Category:Logic]]
 
[[Category:Logic]]
 
[[Category:Logical Graphs]]
 
[[Category:Logical Graphs]]
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Propositional Calculus]]
 
[[Category:Semiotics]]
 
[[Category:Semiotics]]
 
[[Category:Visualization]]
 
[[Category:Visualization]]
12,080

edits