Line 1: |
Line 1: |
− | * | + | ==Differential Logic 2002== |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 1=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | One of the first things that you can do, once you |
| + | have a really decent calculus for boolean functions |
| + | or propositional logic, whatever you want to call it, |
| + | is to compute the differentials of these functions or |
| + | propositions. |
| + | |
| + | Now there are many ways to dance around this idea, |
| + | and I feel like I have tried them all, before one |
| + | gets down to acting on it, and there many issues |
| + | of interpretation and justification that we will |
| + | have to clear up after the fact, that is, before |
| + | we can be sure that it all really makes any sense, |
| + | but I think this time I'll just jump in, and show |
| + | you the form in which this idea first came to me. |
| + | |
| + | Start with a proposition of the form x & y, which |
| + | I graph as two labels attached to a root node, so: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x y | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | x and y | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Written as a string, this is just the concatenation "x y". |
| + | |
| + | The proposition xy may be taken as a boolean function f(x, y) |
| + | having the abstract type f : B x B -> B, where B = {0, 1} is |
| + | read in such a way that 0 means "false" and 1 means "true". |
| + | |
| + | In this style of graphical representation, |
| + | the value "true" looks like a blank label |
| + | and the value "false" looks like an edge. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | true | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | false | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Back to the proposition xy. Imagine yourself standing |
| + | in a fixed cell of the corresponding venn diagram, say, |
| + | the cell where the proposition xy is true, as pictured: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / · \ | |
| + | | / /%\ \ | |
| + | | / /%%%\ \ | |
| + | | / /%%%%%\ \ | |
| + | | / /%%%%%%%\ \ | |
| + | | / /%%%%%%%%%\ \ | |
| + | | o x o%%%%%%%%%%%o y o | |
| + | | \ \%%%%%%%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%%%%%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%%%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%/ / | |
| + | | \ · / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Now ask yourself: What is the value of the |
| + | proposition xy at a distance of dx and dy |
| + | from the cell xy where you are standing? |
| + | |
| + | Don't think about it -- just compute: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx o o dy | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | x o---@---o y | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | (x + dx) and (y + dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | To make future graphs easier to draw in Ascii land, |
| + | I will use devices like @=@=@ and o=o=o to identify |
| + | several nodes into one, as in this next redrawing: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | (x + dx) and (y + dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | However you draw it, these expressions follow because the |
| + | expression x + dx, where the plus sign indicates (mod 2) |
| + | addition in B, and thus corresponds to an exclusive-or |
| + | in logic, parses to a graph of the following form: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx | |
| + | | o---o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | x + dx | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Next question: What is the difference between |
| + | the value of the proposition xy "over there" and |
| + | the value of the proposition xy where you are, all |
| + | expressed as general formula, of course? Here 'tis: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ x y | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | ((x + dx) & (y + dy)) - xy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Oh, I forgot to mention: Computed over B, |
| + | plus and minus are the very same operation. |
| + | This will make the relationship between the |
| + | differential and the integral parts of the |
| + | resulting calculus slightly stranger than |
| + | usual, but never mind that now. |
| + | |
| + | Last question, for now: What is the value of this expression |
| + | from your current standpoint, that is, evaluated at the point |
| + | where xy is true? Well, substituting 1 for x and 1 for y in |
| + | the graph amounts to the same thing as erasing those labels: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | ((1 + dx) & (1 + dy)) - 1·1 | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | And this is equivalent to the following graph: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | dx or dy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Enough for the moment. |
| + | Explanation to follow. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 2=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | We have just met with the fact that |
| + | the differential of the "and" is |
| + | the "or" of the differentials. |
| + | |
| + | x and y --Diff--> dx or dy. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | x y | | |
| + | | @ --Diff--> @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | x y --Diff--> ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | It will be necessary to develop a more refined analysis of |
| + | this statement directly, but that is roughly the nub of it. |
| + | |
| + | If the form of the above statement reminds you of DeMorgan's rule, |
| + | it is no accident, as differentiation and negation turn out to be |
| + | closely related operations. Indeed, one can find discussions of |
| + | logical difference calculus in the Boole-DeMorgan correspondence |
| + | and Peirce also made use of differential operators in a logical |
| + | context, but the exploration of these ideas has been hampered |
| + | by a number of factors, not the least of which being a syntax |
| + | adequate to handle the complexity of expressions that evolve. |
| + | |
| + | For my part, it was definitely a case of the calculus being smarter |
| + | than the calculator thereof. The graphical pictures were catalytic |
| + | in their power over my thinking process, leading me so quickly past |
| + | so many obstructions that I did not have time to think about all of |
| + | the difficulties that would otherwise have inhibited the derivation. |
| + | It did eventually became necessary to write all this up in a linear |
| + | script, and to deal with the various problems of interpretation and |
| + | justification that I could imagine, but that took another 120 pages, |
| + | and so, if you don't like this intuitive approach, then let that be |
| + | your sufficient notice. |
| + | |
| + | Let us run through the initial example again, this time attempting |
| + | to interpret the formulas that develop at each stage along the way. |
| + | |
| + | We begin with a proposition or a boolean function f(x, y) = xy. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / · \ | |
| + | | / /`\ \ | |
| + | | / /```\ \ | |
| + | | / /`````\ \ | |
| + | | / /```````\ \ | |
| + | | / /`````````\ \ | |
| + | | o x o`````f`````o y o | |
| + | | \ \`````````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```````/ / | |
| + | | \ \`````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```/ / | |
| + | | \ \`/ / | |
| + | | \ · / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x y | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | f = x y | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | A function like this has an abstract type and a concrete type. |
| + | The abstract type is what we invoke when we write things like |
| + | f : B x B -> B or f : B^2 -> B. The concrete type takes into |
| + | account the qualitative dimensions or the "units" of the case, |
| + | which can be explained as follows. |
| + | |
| + | 1. Let X be the set of values {(x), x} = {not x, x}. |
| + | |
| + | 2. Let Y be the set of values {(y), y} = {not y, y}. |
| + | |
| + | Then interpret the usual propositions about x, y |
| + | as functions of the concrete type f : X x Y -> B. |
| + | |
| + | We are going to consider various "operators" on these functions. |
| + | Here, an operator F is a function that takes one function f into |
| + | another function Ff. |
| + | |
| + | The first couple of operators that we need to consider are logical analogues |
| + | of those that occur in the classical "finite difference calculus", namely: |
| + | |
| + | 1. The "difference" operator [capital Delta], written here as D. |
| + | |
| + | 2. The "enlargement" operator [capital Epsilon], written here as E. |
| + | |
| + | These days, E is more often called the "shift" operator. |
| + | |
| + | In order to describe the universe in which these operators operate, |
| + | it will be necessary to enlarge our original universe of discourse. |
| + | We mount up from the space U = X x Y to its "differential extension", |
| + | EU = U x dU = X x Y x dX x dY, with dX = {(dx), dx} and dY = {(dy), dy}. |
| + | The interpretations of these new symbols can be diverse, but the easiest |
| + | for now is just to say that dx means "change x" and dy means "change y". |
| + | To draw the differential extension EU of our present universe U = X x Y |
| + | as a venn diagram, it would take us four logical dimensions X, Y, dX, dY, |
| + | but we can project a suggestion of what it's about on the universe X x Y |
| + | by drawing arrows that cross designated borders, labeling the arrows as |
| + | dx when crossing the border between x and (x) and as dy when crossing |
| + | the border between y and (y), in either direction, in either case. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / \ / \ | |
| + | | / · \ | |
| + | | / dy /`\ dx \ | |
| + | | / ^ /```\ ^ \ | |
| + | | / \`````/ \ | |
| + | | / /`\```/`\ \ | |
| + | | / /```\`/```\ \ | |
| + | | o x o`````o`````o y o | |
| + | | \ \`````````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```````/ / | |
| + | | \ \`````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```/ / | |
| + | | \ \`/ / | |
| + | | \ · / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | We can form propositions from these differential variables in the same way |
| + | that we would any other logical variables, for instance, interpreting the |
| + | proposition (dx (dy)) to say "dx => dy", in other words, however you wish |
| + | to take it, whether indicatively or injunctively, as saying something to |
| + | the effect that there is "no change in x without a change in y". |
| + | |
| + | Given the proposition f(x, y) in U = X x Y, |
| + | the (first order) 'enlargement' of f is the |
| + | proposition Ef in EU that is defined by the |
| + | formula Ef(x, y, dx, dy) = f(x + dx, y + dy). |
| + | |
| + | In the example f(x, y) = xy, we obtain: |
| + | |
| + | Ef(x, y, dx, dy) = (x + dx)(y + dy). |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef = (x, dx) (y, dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Given the proposition f(x, y) in U = X x Y, |
| + | the (first order) 'difference' of f is the |
| + | proposition Df in EU that is defined by the |
| + | formula Df = Ef - f, or, written out in full, |
| + | Df(x, y, dx, dy) = f(x + dx, y + dy) - f(x, y). |
| + | |
| + | In the example f(x, y) = xy, the result is: |
| + | |
| + | Df(x, y, dx, dy) = (x + dx)(y + dy) - xy. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ x y | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df = ((x, dx)(y, dy), xy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | We did not yet go through the trouble to interpret this (first order) |
| + | "difference of conjunction" fully, but were happy simply to evaluate |
| + | it with respect to a single location in the universe of discourse, |
| + | namely, at the point picked out by the singular proposition xy, |
| + | in as much as if to say, at the place where x = 1 and y = 1. |
| + | This evaluation is written in the form Df|xy or Df|<1, 1>, |
| + | and we arrived at the locally applicable law that states |
| + | that f = xy = x & y => Df|xy = ((dx)(dy)) = dx or dy. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | ^ | |
| + | | o | o | |
| + | | / \ | / \ | |
| + | | / \|/ \ | |
| + | | /dy | dx\ | |
| + | | /(dx) /|\ (dy)\ | |
| + | | / ^ /`|`\ ^ \ | |
| + | | / \``|``/ \ | |
| + | | / /`\`|`/`\ \ | |
| + | | / /```\|/```\ \ | |
| + | | o x o`````o`````o y o | |
| + | | \ \`````````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```````/ / | |
| + | | \ \`````/ / | |
| + | | \ \```/ / | |
| + | | \ \`/ / | |
| + | | \ · / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df|xy = ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | The picture illustrates the analysis of the inclusive disjunction ((dx)(dy)) |
| + | into the exclusive disjunction: dx(dy) + dy(dx) + dx dy, a proposition that |
| + | may be interpreted to say "change x or change y or both". And this can be |
| + | recognized as just what you need to do if you happen to find yourself in |
| + | the center cell and desire a detailed description of ways to depart it. |
| + | |
| + | Jon Awbrey -- |
| + | |
| + | Formerly Of: |
| + | Center Cell, |
| + | Chateau Dif. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 3=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | Last time we computed what will variously be called |
| + | the "difference map", the "difference proposition", |
| + | or the "local proposition" Df_p for the proposition |
| + | f(x, y) = xy at the point p where x = 1 and y = 1. |
| + | |
| + | In the universe U = X x Y, the four propositions |
| + | xy, x(y), (x)y, (x)(y) that indicate the "cells", |
| + | or the smallest regions of the venn diagram, are |
| + | called "singular propositions". These serve as |
| + | an alternative notation for naming the points |
| + | <1, 1>, <1, 0>, <0, 1>, <0, 0>, respectively. |
| + | |
| + | Thus, we can write Df_p = Df|p = Df|<1, 1> = Df|xy, |
| + | so long as we know the frame of reference in force. |
| + | |
| + | Sticking with the example f(x, y) = xy, let us compute the |
| + | value of the difference proposition Df at all of the points. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ x y | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df = ((x, dx)(y, dy), xy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df|xy = ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | dx | dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / o | |
| + | | \| |/ | | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df|x(y) = (dx) dy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | dx dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / o | |
| + | | \| |/ | | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df|(x)y = dx (dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | dx | dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / o o | |
| + | | \| |/ \ / | |
| + | | o=o-----------o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Df|(x)(y) = dx dy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | The easy way to visualize the values of these graphical |
| + | expressions is just to notice the following equivalents: |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x | |
| + | | o-o-o-...-o-o-o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / x | |
| + | | \ / o | |
| + | | \ / | | |
| + | | @ = @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | (x, , ... , , ) = (x) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | x_1 x_2 x_k | | |
| + | | o---o-...-o---o | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / x_1 ... x_k | |
| + | | @ = @ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | (x_1, ..., x_k, ()) = x_1 · ... · x_k | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Laying out the arrows on the augmented venn diagram, |
| + | one gets a picture of a "differential vector field". |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | ^ | |
| + | | o | o | |
| + | | / \ | / \ | |
| + | | / \|/ \ | |
| + | | /dy | dx\ | |
| + | | /(dx) /|\ (dy)\ | |
| + | | / ^ /`|`\ ^ \ | |
| + | | / \``|``/ \ | |
| + | | / /`\`|`/`\ \ | |
| + | | / /```\|/```\ \ | |
| + | | o x o`````o`````o y o | |
| + | | \ \`````````/ / | |
| + | | \ o---->```<----o / | |
| + | | \ dy \``^``/ dx / | |
| + | | \(dx) \`|`/ (dy)/ | |
| + | | \ \|/ / | |
| + | | \ | / | |
| + | | \ /|\ / | |
| + | | \ / | \ / | |
| + | | o | o | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | dx | dy | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | This really just constitutes a depiction of |
| + | the interpretations in EU = X x Y x dX x dY |
| + | that satisfy the difference proposition Df, |
| + | namely, these: |
| + | |
| + | 1. x y dx dy |
| + | 2. x y dx (dy) |
| + | 3. x y (dx) dy |
| + | 4. x (y)(dx) dy |
| + | 5. (x) y dx (dy) |
| + | 6. (x)(y) dx dy |
| + | |
| + | By inspection, it is fairly easy to understand Df |
| + | as telling you what you have to do from each point |
| + | of U in order to change the value borne by f(x, y). |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 4=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | We have been studying the action of the difference operator D, |
| + | also known as the "localization operator", on the proposition |
| + | f : X x Y -> B that is commonly known as the conjunction x·y. |
| + | We described Df as a (first order) differential proposition, |
| + | that is, a proposition of the type Df : X x Y x dX x dY -> B. |
| + | Abstracting from the augmented venn diagram that illustrates |
| + | how the "models", or the "satisfying interpretations", of Df |
| + | distribute within the extended universe EU = X x Y x dX x dY, |
| + | we can depict Df in the form of a "digraph" or directed graph, |
| + | one whose points are labeled with the elements of U = X x Y |
| + | and whose arrows are labeled with the elements of dU = dX x dY. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x · y | |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | ^^^ | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | (dx)· dy / | \ dx ·(dy) | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | v | v | |
| + | | x ·(y) o | o (x)· y | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | dx · dy | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | v | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | |
| + | | (x)·(y) | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | f = x y | |
| + | | | |
| + | | Df = x y · ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + x (y) · (dx) dy | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + (x) y · dx (dy) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + (x)(y) · dx dy | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Any proposition worth its salt, as they say, |
| + | has many equivalent ways to look at it, any |
| + | of which may reveal some unsuspected aspect |
| + | of its meaning. We will encounter more and |
| + | more of these alternative readings as we go. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 5=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | The enlargement operator E, also known as the "shift operator", |
| + | has many interesting and very useful properties in its own right, |
| + | so let us not fail to observe a few of the more salient features |
| + | that play out on the surface of our simple example, f(x, y) = xy. |
| + | |
| + | Introduce a suitably generic definition of the extended universe of discourse: |
| + | |
| + | Let U = X_1 x ... x X_k and EU = U x dU = X_1 x ... x X_k x dX_1 x ... x dX_k. |
| + | |
| + | For a proposition f : X_1 x ... x X_k -> B, |
| + | the (first order) 'enlargement' of f is the |
| + | proposition Ef : EU -> B that is defined by: |
| + | |
| + | Ef(x_1, ..., x_k, dx_1, ..., dx_k) = f(x_1 + dx_1, ..., x_k + dx_k). |
| + | |
| + | It should be noted that the so-called "differential variables" dx_j |
| + | are really just the same kind of boolean variables as the other x_j. |
| + | It is conventional to give the additional variables these brands of |
| + | inflected names, but whatever extra connotations we might choose to |
| + | attach to these syntactic conveniences are wholly external to their |
| + | purely algebraic meanings. |
| + | |
| + | For the example f(x, y) = xy, we obtain: |
| + | |
| + | Ef(x, y, dx, dy) = (x + dx)(y + dy). |
| + | |
| + | Given that this expression uses nothing more than the "boolean ring" |
| + | operations of addition (+) and multiplication (·), it is permissible |
| + | to "multiply things out" in the usual manner to arrive at the result: |
| + | |
| + | Ef(x, y, dx, dy) = x·y + x·dy + y·dx + dx·dy. |
| + | |
| + | To understand what this means in logical terms, for instance, as expressed |
| + | in a boolean expansion or a "disjunctive normal form" (DNF), it is perhaps |
| + | a little better to go back and analyze the expression the same way that we |
| + | did for Df. Thus, let us compute the value of the enlarged proposition Ef |
| + | at each of the points in the universe of discourse U = X x Y. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x dx y dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef = (x, dx)·(y, dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | dx dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef|xy = (dx)·(dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | dx | dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef|x(y) = (dx)· dy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | dx dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef|(x)y = dx ·(dy) | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | dx | dy | |
| + | | o---o o---o | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \ | | / | |
| + | | \| |/ | |
| + | | @=@ | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | Ef|(x)(y) = dx · dy | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | Given the sort of data that arises from this form of analysis, |
| + | we can now fold the disjoined ingredients back into a boolean |
| + | expansion or a DNF that is equivalent to the proposition Ef. |
| + | |
| + | Ef = xy · Ef_xy + x(y) · Ef_x(y) + (x)y · Ef_(x)y + (x)(y) · Ef_(x)(y). |
| + | |
| + | Here is a summary of the result, illustrated by means of a digraph picture, |
| + | where the "no change" element (dx)(dy) is drawn as a loop at the point x·y. |
| + | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | x · y | |
| + | | (dx)·(dy) | |
| + | | -->-- | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | \ / | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | ^^^ | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | (dx)· dy / | \ dx ·(dy) | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | / | \ | |
| + | | x ·(y) o | o (x)· y | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | dx · dy | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | | | |
| + | | o | |
| + | | | |
| + | | (x)·(y) | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | f = x y | |
| + | | | |
| + | | Ef = x y · (dx)(dy) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + x (y) · (dx) dy | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + (x) y · dx (dy) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | + (x)(y) · dx dy | |
| + | | | |
| + | o---------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | We may understand the enlarged proposition Ef |
| + | as telling us all the different ways to reach |
| + | a model of f from any point of the universe U. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 6=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | To broaden our experience with simple examples, let us now contemplate the |
| + | sixteen functions of concrete type X x Y -> B and abstract type B x B -> B. |
| + | For future reference, I will set here a few tables that detail the actions |
| + | of E and D and on each of these functions, allowing us to view the results |
| + | in several different ways. |
| + | |
| + | By way of initial orientation, Table 0 lists equivalent expressions for the |
| + | sixteen functions in a number of different languages for zeroth order logic. |
| + | |
| + | Table 0. Propositional Forms On Two Variables |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o----------o------------------o----------o |
| + | | L_1 | L_2 | L_3 | L_4 | L_5 | L_6 | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | Decimal | Binary | Vector | Cactus | English | Vulgate | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o----------o------------------o----------o |
| + | | | x = 1 1 0 0 | | | | |
| + | | | y = 1 0 1 0 | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o----------o------------------o----------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | f_0000 | 0 0 0 0 | () | false | 0 | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | f_0001 | 0 0 0 1 | (x)(y) | neither x nor y | ~x & ~y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | f_0010 | 0 0 1 0 | (x) y | y and not x | ~x & y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | f_0011 | 0 0 1 1 | (x) | not x | ~x | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | f_0100 | 0 1 0 0 | x (y) | x and not y | x & ~y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | f_0101 | 0 1 0 1 | (y) | not y | ~y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | f_0110 | 0 1 1 0 | (x, y) | x not equal to y | x + y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | f_0111 | 0 1 1 1 | (x y) | not both x and y | ~x v ~y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | f_1000 | 1 0 0 0 | x y | x and y | x & y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | f_1001 | 1 0 0 1 | ((x, y)) | x equal to y | x = y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | f_1010 | 1 0 1 0 | y | y | y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | f_1011 | 1 0 1 1 | (x (y)) | not x without y | x => y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | f_1100 | 1 1 0 0 | x | x | x | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | f_1101 | 1 1 0 1 | ((x) y) | not y without x | x <= y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | f_1110 | 1 1 1 0 | ((x)(y)) | x or y | x v y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | f_1111 | 1 1 1 1 | (()) | true | 1 | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o----------o------------------o----------o |
| + | |
| + | The next four Tables expand the expressions of Ef and Df |
| + | in two different ways, for each of the sixteen functions. |
| + | Notice that the functions are given in a different order, |
| + | here being collected into a set of seven natural classes. |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Ef Expanded Over Ordinary Features {x, y} |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | f | Ef | xy | Ef | x(y) | Ef | (x)y | Ef | (x)(y)| |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | () | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | (x)(y) | dx dy | dx (dy) | (dx) dy | (dx)(dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | (x) y | dx (dy) | dx dy | (dx)(dy) | (dx) dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | x (y) | (dx) dy | (dx)(dy) | dx dy | dx (dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | x y | (dx)(dy) | (dx) dy | dx (dy) | dx dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | (x) | dx | dx | (dx) | (dx) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | x | (dx) | (dx) | dx | dx | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | (x, y) | (dx, dy) | ((dx, dy)) | ((dx, dy)) | (dx, dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | ((x, y)) | ((dx, dy)) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | ((dx, dy)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | (y) | dy | (dy) | dy | (dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | y | (dy) | dy | (dy) | dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | (x y) | ((dx)(dy)) | ((dx) dy) | (dx (dy)) | (dx dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | (x (y)) | ((dx) dy) | ((dx)(dy)) | (dx dy) | (dx (dy)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | ((x) y) | (dx (dy)) | (dx dy) | ((dx)(dy)) | ((dx) dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | ((x)(y)) | (dx dy) | (dx (dy)) | ((dx) dy) | ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | |
| + | |
| + | Table 2. Df Expanded Over Ordinary Features {x, y} |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | f | Df | xy | Df | x(y) | Df | (x)y | Df | (x)(y)| |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | () | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | (x)(y) | dx dy | dx (dy) | (dx) dy | ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | (x) y | dx (dy) | dx dy | ((dx)(dy)) | (dx) dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | x (y) | (dx) dy | ((dx)(dy)) | dx dy | dx (dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | x y | ((dx)(dy)) | (dx) dy | dx (dy) | dx dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | (x) | dx | dx | dx | dx | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | x | dx | dx | dx | dx | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | (x, y) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | ((x, y)) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | (dx, dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | (y) | dy | dy | dy | dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | y | dy | dy | dy | dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | (x y) | ((dx)(dy)) | (dx) dy | dx (dy) | dx dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | (x (y)) | (dx) dy | ((dx)(dy)) | dx dy | dx (dy) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | ((x) y) | dx (dy) | dx dy | ((dx)(dy)) | (dx) dy | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | ((x)(y)) | dx dy | dx (dy) | (dx) dy | ((dx)(dy)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | (()) | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | |
| + | |
| + | Table 3. Ef Expanded Over Differential Features {dx, dy} |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | f | T_11 f | T_10 f | T_01 f | T_00 f | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | Ef| dx·dy | Ef| dx(dy) | Ef| (dx)dy | Ef|(dx)(dy)| |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | () | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | (x)(y) | x y | x (y) | (x) y | (x)(y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | (x) y | x (y) | x y | (x)(y) | (x) y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | x (y) | (x) y | (x)(y) | x y | x (y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | x y | (x)(y) | (x) y | x (y) | x y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | (x) | x | x | (x) | (x) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | x | (x) | (x) | x | x | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | (x, y) | (x, y) | ((x, y)) | ((x, y)) | (x, y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | ((x, y)) | ((x, y)) | (x, y) | (x, y) | ((x, y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | (y) | y | (y) | y | (y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | y | (y) | y | (y) | y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | (x y) | ((x)(y)) | ((x) y) | (x (y)) | (x y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | (x (y)) | ((x) y) | ((x)(y)) | (x y) | (x (y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | ((x) y) | (x (y)) | (x y) | ((x)(y)) | ((x) y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | ((x)(y)) | (x y) | (x (y)) | ((x) y) | ((x)(y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | | Fixed Point Total | 4 | 4 | 4 | 16 | |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | o-------------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | |
| + | |
| + | Table 4. Df Expanded Over Differential Features {dx, dy} |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | f | Df| dx·dy | Df| dx(dy) | Df| (dx)dy | Df|(dx)(dy)| |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | () | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | (x)(y) | ((x, y)) | (y) | (x) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | (x) y | (x, y) | y | (x) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | x (y) | (x, y) | (y) | x | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | x y | ((x, y)) | y | x | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | (x) | (()) | (()) | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | x | (()) | (()) | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | (x, y) | () | (()) | (()) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | ((x, y)) | () | (()) | (()) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | (y) | (()) | () | (()) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | y | (()) | () | (()) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | (x y) | ((x, y)) | y | x | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | (x (y)) | (x, y) | (y) | x | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | ((x) y) | (x, y) | y | (x) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | ((x)(y)) | ((x, y)) | (y) | (x) | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | (()) | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | |
| + | If the medium is truly the message, |
| + | the blank slate is the innate idea. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 7=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | If you think that I linger in the realm of logical difference calculus |
| + | out of sheer vacillation about getting down to the differential proper, |
| + | it is probably out of a prior expectation that you derive from the art |
| + | or the long-engrained practice of real analysis. But the fact is that |
| + | ordinary calculus only rushes on to the sundry orders of approximation |
| + | because the strain of comprehending the full import of E and D at once |
| + | whelm over its discrete and finite powers to grasp them. But here, in |
| + | the fully serene idylls of ZOL, we find ourselves fit with the compass |
| + | of a wit that is all we'd ever wish to explore their effects with care. |
| + | |
| + | So let us do just that. |
| + | |
| + | I will first rationalize the novel grouping of propositional forms |
| + | in the last set of Tables, as that will extend a gentle invitation |
| + | to the mathematical subject of "group theory", and demonstrate its |
| + | relevance to differential logic in a strikingly apt and useful way. |
| + | The data for that account is contained in Table 3. |
| + | |
| + | Table 3. Ef Expanded Over Differential Features {dx, dy} |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | f | T_11 f | T_10 f | T_01 f | T_00 f | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | Ef| dx·dy | Ef| dx(dy) | Ef| (dx)dy | Ef|(dx)(dy)| |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_0 | () | () | () | () | () | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_1 | (x)(y) | x y | x (y) | (x) y | (x)(y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_2 | (x) y | x (y) | x y | (x)(y) | (x) y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_4 | x (y) | (x) y | (x)(y) | x y | x (y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_8 | x y | (x)(y) | (x) y | x (y) | x y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_3 | (x) | x | x | (x) | (x) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_12 | x | (x) | (x) | x | x | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_6 | (x, y) | (x, y) | ((x, y)) | ((x, y)) | (x, y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_9 | ((x, y)) | ((x, y)) | (x, y) | (x, y) | ((x, y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_5 | (y) | y | (y) | y | (y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_10 | y | (y) | y | (y) | y | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_7 | (x y) | ((x)(y)) | ((x) y) | (x (y)) | (x y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_11 | (x (y)) | ((x) y) | ((x)(y)) | (x y) | (x (y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_13 | ((x) y) | (x (y)) | (x y) | ((x)(y)) | ((x) y) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_14 | ((x)(y)) | (x y) | (x (y)) | ((x) y) | ((x)(y)) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | f_15 | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | (()) | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o------o------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | | Fixed Point Total | 4 | 4 | 4 | 16 | |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | o-------------------o------------o------------o------------o------------o |
| + | |
| + | The shift operator E can be understood as enacting a substitution operation |
| + | on the proposition that is given as its argument. In our immediate example, |
| + | we have the following data and definition: |
| + | |
| + | E : (U -> B) -> (EU -> B), |
| + | |
| + | E : f(x, y) -> Ef(x, y, dx, dy), |
| + | |
| + | Ef(x, y, dx, dy) = f(x + dx, y + dy). |
| + | |
| + | Therefore, if we evaluate Ef at particular values of dx and dy, |
| + | for example, dx = i and dy = j, where i, j are in B, we obtain: |
| + | |
| + | E_ij : (U -> B) -> (U -> B), |
| + | |
| + | E_ij : f -> E_ij f, |
| + | |
| + | E_ij f = Ef | <dx = i, dy = j> = f(x + i, y + j). |
| + | |
| + | The notation is a little bit awkward, but the data of the Table should |
| + | make the sense clear. The important thing to observe is that E_ij has |
| + | the effect of transforming each proposition f : U -> B into some other |
| + | proposition f' : U -> B. As it happens, the action is one-to-one and |
| + | onto for each E_ij, so the gang of four operators {E_ij : i, j in B} |
| + | is an example of what is called a "transformation group" on the set |
| + | of sixteen propositions. Bowing to a longstanding local and linear |
| + | tradition, I will therefore redub the four elements of this group |
| + | as T_00, T_01, T_10, T_11, to bear in mind their transformative |
| + | character, or nature, as the case may be. Abstractly viewed, |
| + | this group of order four has the following operation table: |
| + | |
| + | o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | · % T_00 | T_01 | T_10 | T_11 | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o==========o==========o==========o==========o==========o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | T_00 % T_00 | T_01 | T_10 | T_11 | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | T_01 % T_01 | T_00 | T_11 | T_10 | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | T_10 % T_10 | T_11 | T_00 | T_01 | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | T_11 % T_11 | T_10 | T_01 | T_00 | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o----------o----------o----------o----------o----------o |
| + | |
| + | It happens that there are just two possible groups of 4 elements. |
| + | One is the cyclic group Z_4 (German "Zyklus"), which this is not. |
| + | The other is Klein's four-group V_4 (German "Vier"), which it is. |
| + | |
| + | More concretely viewed, the group as a whole pushes the set |
| + | of sixteen propositions around in such a way that they fall |
| + | into seven natural classes, called "orbits". One says that |
| + | the orbits are preserved by the action of the group. There |
| + | is an "Orbit Lemma" of immense utility to "those who count" |
| + | which, depending on your upbringing, you may associate with |
| + | the names of Burnside, Cauchy, Frobenius, or some subset or |
| + | superset of these three, vouching that the number of orbits |
| + | is equal to the mean number of fixed points, in other words, |
| + | the total number of points (in our case, propositions) that |
| + | are left unmoved by the separate operations, divided by the |
| + | order of the group. In this instance, T_00 operates as the |
| + | group identity, fixing all 16 propositions, while the other |
| + | three group elements fix 4 propositions each, and so we get: |
| + | Number of orbits = (4 + 4 + 4 + 16) / 4 = 7. Amazing! |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 8=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | We have been contemplating functions of the type f : U -> B |
| + | studying the action of the operators E and D on this family. |
| + | These functions, that we may identify for our present aims |
| + | with propositions, inasmuch as they capture their abstract |
| + | forms, are logical analogues of "scalar potential fields". |
| + | These are the sorts of fields that are so picturesquely |
| + | presented in elementary calculus and physics textbooks |
| + | by images of snow-covered hills and parties of skiers |
| + | who trek down their slopes like least action heroes. |
| + | The analogous scene in propositional logic presents |
| + | us with forms more reminiscent of plateaunic idylls, |
| + | being all plains at one of two levels, the mesas of |
| + | verity and falsity, as it were, with nary a niche |
| + | to inhabit between them, restricting our options |
| + | for a sporting gradient of downhill dynamics to |
| + | just one of two, standing still on level ground |
| + | or falling off a bluff. |
| + | |
| + | We are still working well within the logical analogue of the |
| + | classical finite difference calculus, taking in the novelties |
| + | that the logical transmutation of familiar elements is able to |
| + | bring to light. Soon we will take up several different notions |
| + | of approximation relationships that may be seen to organize the |
| + | space of propositions, and these will allow us to define several |
| + | different forms of differential analysis applying to propositions. |
| + | In time we will find reason to consider more general types of maps, |
| + | having concrete types of the form X_1 x ... x X_k -> Y_1 x ... x Y_n |
| + | and abstract types B^k -> B^n. We will think of these mappings as |
| + | transforming universes of discourse into themselves or into others, |
| + | in short, as "transformations of discourse". |
| + | |
| + | Before we continue with this intinerary, however, I would like to highlight |
| + | another sort of "differential aspect" that concerns the "boundary operator" |
| + | or the "marked connective" that serves as one of the two basic connectives |
| + | in the cactus language for ZOL. |
| + | |
| + | For example, consider the proposition f of concrete type f : X x Y x Z -> B |
| + | and abstract type f : B^3 -> B that is written "(x, y, z)" in cactus syntax. |
| + | Taken as an assertion in what Peirce called the "existential interpretation", |
| + | (x, y, z) says that just one of x, y, z is false. It is useful to consider |
| + | this assertion in relation to the conjunction xyz of the features that are |
| + | engaged as its arguments. A venn diagram of (x, y, z) looks like this: |
| + | |
| + | o-----------------------------------------------------------o |
| + | | U | |
| + | | | |
| + | | o-------------o | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | o x o | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | o--o----------o o----------o--o | |
| + | | / \%%%%%%%%%%\ /%%%%%%%%%%/ \ | |
| + | | / \%%%%%%%%%%o%%%%%%%%%%/ \ | |
| + | | / \%%%%%%%%/ \%%%%%%%%/ \ | |
| + | | / \%%%%%%/ \%%%%%%/ \ | |
| + | | / \%%%%/ \%%%%/ \ | |
| + | | o o--o-------o--o o | |
| + | | | |%%%%%%%| | | |
| + | | | |%%%%%%%| | | |
| + | | | |%%%%%%%| | | |
| + | | | |%%%%%%%| | | |
| + | | | |%%%%%%%| | | |
| + | | o y o%%%%%%%o z o | |
| + | | \ \%%%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%%%/ / | |
| + | | \ \%/ / | |
| + | | \ o / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o-------------o o-------------o | |
| + | | | |
| + | | | |
| + | o-----------------------------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | In relation to the center cell indicated by the conjunction xyz, |
| + | the region indicated by (x, y, z) is comprised of the "adjacent" |
| + | or the "bordering" cells. Thus they are the cells that are just |
| + | across the boundary of the center cell, as if reached by way of |
| + | Leibniz's "minimal changes" from the point of origin, here, xyz. |
| + | |
| + | The same sort of boundary relationship holds for any cell of origin that |
| + | one might elect to indicate, say, by means of the conjunction of positive |
| + | or negative basis features u_1 · ... · u_k, with u_j = x_j or u_j = (x_j), |
| + | for j = 1 to k. The proposition (u_1, ..., u_k) indicates the disjunctive |
| + | region consisting of the cells that are just next door to u_1 · ... · u_k. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 9=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might conceivably have |
| + | | practical bearings you conceive the objects of your |
| + | | conception to have. Then, your conception of those |
| + | | effects is the whole of your conception of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, "The Maxim of Pragmatism, CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | One other subject that it would be opportune to mention at this point, |
| + | while we have an object example of a mathematical group fresh in mind, |
| + | is the relationship between the pragmatic maxim and what are commonly |
| + | known in mathematics as "representation principles". As it turns out, |
| + | with regard to its formal characteristics, the pragmatic maxim unites |
| + | the aspects of a representation principle with the attributes of what |
| + | would ordinarily be known as a "closure principle". We will consider |
| + | the form of closure that is invoked by the pragmatic maxim on another |
| + | occasion, focusing here and now on the topic of group representations. |
| + | |
| + | Let us return to the example of the so-called "four-group" V_4. |
| + | We encountered this group in one of its concrete representations, |
| + | namely, as a "transformation group" that acts on a set of objects, |
| + | in this particular case a set of sixteen functions or propositions. |
| + | Forgetting about the set of objects that the group transforms among |
| + | themselves, we may take the abstract view of the group's operational |
| + | structure, say, in the form of the group operation table copied here: |
| + | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | · % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | e % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | f % f | e | h | g | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | g % g | h | e | f | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | h % h | g | f | e | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | This table is abstractly the same as, or isomorphic to, the versions with |
| + | the E_ij operators and the T_ij transformations that we discussed earlier. |
| + | That is to say, the story is the same -- only the names have been changed. |
| + | An abstract group can have a multitude of significantly and superficially |
| + | different representations. Even after we have long forgotten the details |
| + | of the particular representation that we may have come in with, there are |
| + | species of concrete representations, called the "regular representations", |
| + | that are always readily available, as they can be generated from the mere |
| + | data of the abstract operation table itself. |
| + | |
| + | For example, select a group element from the top margin of the Table, |
| + | and "consider its effects" on each of the group elements as they are |
| + | listed along the left margin. We may record these effects as Peirce |
| + | usually did, as a logical "aggregate" of elementary dyadic relatives, |
| + | that is to say, a disjunction or a logical sum whose terms represent |
| + | the ordered pairs of <input : output> transactions that are produced |
| + | by each group element in turn. This yields what is usually known as |
| + | one of the "regular representations" of the group, specifically, the |
| + | "first", the "post-", or the "right" regular representation. It has |
| + | long been conventional to organize the terms in the form of a matrix: |
| + | |
| + | Reading "+" as a logical disjunction: |
| + | |
| + | G = e + f + g + h, |
| + | |
| + | And so, by expanding effects, we get: |
| + | |
| + | G = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | + e:f + f:e + g:h + h:g |
| + | |
| + | + e:g + f:h + g:e + h:f |
| + | |
| + | + e:h + f:g + g:f + h:e |
| + | |
| + | More on the pragmatic maxim as a representation principle later. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 10=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might conceivably have |
| + | | practical bearings you conceive the objects of your |
| + | | conception to have. Then, your conception of those |
| + | | effects is the whole of your conception of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, "The Maxim of Pragmatism, CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | The genealogy of this conception of pragmatic representation is very intricate. |
| + | I will delineate some details that I presently fancy I remember clearly enough, |
| + | subject to later correction. Without checking historical accounts, I will not |
| + | be able to pin down anything like a real chronology, but most of these notions |
| + | were standard furnishings of the 19th Century mathematical study, and only the |
| + | last few items date as late as the 1920's. |
| + | |
| + | The idea about the regular representations of a group is universally known |
| + | as "Cayley's Theorem", usually in the form: "Every group is isomorphic to |
| + | a subgroup of Aut(S), the group of automorphisms of an appropriate set S". |
| + | There is a considerable generalization of these regular representations to |
| + | a broad class of relational algebraic systems in Peirce's earliest papers. |
| + | The crux of the whole idea is this: |
| + | |
| + | | Consider the effects of the symbol, whose meaning you wish to investigate, |
| + | | as they play out on "all" of the different stages of context on which you |
| + | | can imagine that symbol playing a role. |
| + | |
| + | This idea of contextual definition is basically the same as Jeremy Bentham's |
| + | notion of "paraphrasis", a "method of accounting for fictions by explaining |
| + | various purported terms away" (Quine, in Van Heijenoort, page 216). Today |
| + | we'd call these constructions "term models". This, again, is the big idea |
| + | behind Schönfinkel's combinators {S, K, I}, and hence of lambda calculus, |
| + | and I reckon you know where that leads. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 11=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | Continuing to draw on the reduced example of group representations, |
| + | I would like to draw out a few of the finer points and problems of |
| + | regarding the maxim of pragmatism as a principle of representation. |
| + | |
| + | Let us revisit the example of an abstract group that we had befour: |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Klein Four-Group V_4 |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | · % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | e % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | f % f | e | h | g | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | g % g | h | e | f | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | h % h | g | f | e | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | I presented the regular post-representation |
| + | of the four-group V_4 in the following form: |
| + | |
| + | Reading "+" as a logical disjunction: |
| + | |
| + | G = e + f + g + h |
| + | |
| + | And so, by expanding effects, we get: |
| + | |
| + | G = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | + e:f + f:e + g:h + h:g |
| + | |
| + | + e:g + f:h + g:e + h:f |
| + | |
| + | + e:h + f:g + g:f + h:e |
| + | |
| + | This presents the group in one big bunch, |
| + | and there are occasions when one regards |
| + | it this way, but that is not the typical |
| + | form of presentation that we'd encounter. |
| + | More likely, the story would go a little |
| + | bit like this: |
| + | |
| + | I cannot remember any of my math teachers |
| + | ever invoking the pragmatic maxim by name, |
| + | but it would be a very regular occurrence |
| + | for such mentors and tutors to set up the |
| + | subject in this wise: Suppose you forget |
| + | what a given abstract group element means, |
| + | that is, in effect, 'what it is'. Then a |
| + | sure way to jog your sense of 'what it is' |
| + | is to build a regular representation from |
| + | the formal materials that are necessarily |
| + | left lying about on that abstraction site. |
| + | |
| + | Working through the construction for each |
| + | one of the four group elements, we arrive |
| + | at the following exegeses of their senses, |
| + | giving their regular post-representations: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | f = e:f + f:e + g:h + h:g |
| + | |
| + | g = e:g + f:h + g:e + h:f |
| + | |
| + | h = e:h + f:g + g:f + h:e |
| + | |
| + | So if somebody asks you, say, "What is g?", |
| + | you can say, "I don't know for certain but |
| + | in practice its effects go a bit like this: |
| + | Converting e to g, f to h, g to e, h to f". |
| + | |
| + | I will have to check this out later on, but my impression is |
| + | that Peirce tended to lean toward the other brand of regular, |
| + | the "second", the "left", or the "ante-representation" of the |
| + | groups that he treated in his earliest manuscripts and papers. |
| + | I believe that this was because he thought of the actions on |
| + | the pattern of dyadic relative terms like the "aftermath of". |
| + | |
| + | Working through this alternative for each |
| + | one of the four group elements, we arrive |
| + | at the following exegeses of their senses, |
| + | giving their regular ante-representations: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | f = f:e + e:f + h:g + g:h |
| + | |
| + | g = g:e + h:f + e:g + f:h |
| + | |
| + | h = h:e + g:f + f:g + e:h |
| + | |
| + | Your paraphrastic interpretation of what this all |
| + | means would come out precisely the same as before. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 12=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | Erratum |
| + | |
| + | Oops! I think that I have just confounded two entirely different issues: |
| + | 1. The substantial difference between right and left regular representations. |
| + | 2. The inessential difference between two conventions of presenting matrices. |
| + | I will sort this out and correct it later, as need be. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 13=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | Let me return to Peirce's early papers on the algebra of relatives |
| + | to pick up the conventions that he used there, and then rewrite my |
| + | account of regular representations in a way that conforms to those. |
| + | |
| + | Peirce expresses the action of an "elementary dual relative" like so: |
| + | |
| + | | [Let] A:B be taken to denote |
| + | | the elementary relative which |
| + | | multiplied into B gives A. |
| + | | |
| + | | Peirce, 'Collected Papers', CP 3.123. |
| + | |
| + | And though he is well aware that it is not at all necessary to arrange |
| + | elementary relatives into arrays, matrices, or tables, when he does so |
| + | he tends to prefer organizing dyadic relations in the following manner: |
| + | |
| + | | A:A A:B A:C | |
| + | | | |
| + | | B:A B:B B:C | |
| + | | | |
| + | | C:A C:B C:C | |
| + | |
| + | That conforms to the way that the last school of thought |
| + | I matriculated into stipulated that we tabulate material: |
| + | |
| + | | e_11 e_12 e_13 | |
| + | | | |
| + | | e_21 e_22 e_23 | |
| + | | | |
| + | | e_31 e_32 e_33 | |
| + | |
| + | So, for example, let us suppose that we have the small universe {A, B, C}, |
| + | and the 2-adic relation m = "mover of" that is represented by this matrix: |
| + | |
| + | m = |
| + | |
| + | | m_AA (A:A) m_AB (A:B) m_AC (A:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | m_BA (B:A) m_BB (B:B) m_BC (B:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | m_CA (C:A) m_CB (C:B) m_CC (C:C) | |
| + | |
| + | Also, let m be such that |
| + | A is a mover of A and B, |
| + | B is a mover of B and C, |
| + | C is a mover of C and A. |
| + | |
| + | In sum: |
| + | |
| + | m = |
| + | |
| + | | 1 · (A:A) 1 · (A:B) 0 · (A:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 0 · (B:A) 1 · (B:B) 1 · (B:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 1 · (C:A) 0 · (C:B) 1 · (C:C) | |
| + | |
| + | For the sake of orientation and motivation, |
| + | compare with Peirce's notation in CP 3.329. |
| + | |
| + | I think that will serve to fix notation |
| + | and set up the remainder of the account. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 14=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | I am beginning to see how I got confused. |
| + | It is common in algebra to switch around |
| + | between different conventions of display, |
| + | as the momentary fancy happens to strike, |
| + | and I see that Peirce is no different in |
| + | this sort of shiftiness than anyone else. |
| + | A changeover appears to occur especially |
| + | whenever he shifts from logical contexts |
| + | to algebraic contexts of application. |
| + | |
| + | In the paper "On the Relative Forms of Quaternions" (CP 3.323), |
| + | we observe Peirce providing the following sorts of explanation: |
| + | |
| + | | If X, Y, Z denote the three rectangular components of a vector, and W denote |
| + | | numerical unity (or a fourth rectangular component, involving space of four |
| + | | dimensions), and (Y:Z) denote the operation of converting the Y component |
| + | | of a vector into its Z component, then |
| + | | |
| + | | 1 = (W:W) + (X:X) + (Y:Y) + (Z:Z) |
| + | | |
| + | | i = (X:W) - (W:X) - (Y:Z) + (Z:Y) |
| + | | |
| + | | j = (Y:W) - (W:Y) - (Z:X) + (X:Z) |
| + | | |
| + | | k = (Z:W) - (W:Z) - (X:Y) + (Y:X) |
| + | | |
| + | | In the language of logic (Y:Z) is a relative term whose relate is |
| + | | a Y component, and whose correlate is a Z component. The law of |
| + | | multiplication is plainly (Y:Z)(Z:X) = (Y:X), (Y:Z)(X:W) = 0, |
| + | | and the application of these rules to the above values of |
| + | | 1, i, j, k gives the quaternion relations |
| + | | |
| + | | i^2 = j^2 = k^2 = -1, |
| + | | |
| + | | ijk = -1, |
| + | | |
| + | | etc. |
| + | | |
| + | | The symbol a(Y:Z) denotes the changing of Y to Z and the |
| + | | multiplication of the result by 'a'. If the relatives be |
| + | | arranged in a block |
| + | | |
| + | | W:W W:X W:Y W:Z |
| + | | |
| + | | X:W X:X X:Y X:Z |
| + | | |
| + | | Y:W Y:X Y:Y Y:Z |
| + | | |
| + | | Z:W Z:X Z:Y Z:Z |
| + | | |
| + | | then the quaternion w + xi + yj + zk |
| + | | is represented by the matrix of numbers |
| + | | |
| + | | w -x -y -z |
| + | | |
| + | | x w -z y |
| + | | |
| + | | y z w -x |
| + | | |
| + | | z -y x w |
| + | | |
| + | | The multiplication of such matrices follows the same laws as the |
| + | | multiplication of quaternions. The determinant of the matrix = |
| + | | the fourth power of the tensor of the quaternion. |
| + | | |
| + | | The imaginary x + y(-1)^(1/2) may likewise be represented by the matrix |
| + | | |
| + | | x y |
| + | | |
| + | | -y x |
| + | | |
| + | | and the determinant of the matrix = the square of the modulus. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, 'Collected Papers', CP 3.323. |
| + | |'Johns Hopkins University Circulars', No. 13, p. 179, 1882. |
| + | |
| + | This way of talking is the mark of a person who opts |
| + | to multiply his matrices "on the rignt", as they say. |
| + | Yet Peirce still continues to call the first element |
| + | of the ordered pair (I:J) its "relate" while calling |
| + | the second element of the pair (I:J) its "correlate". |
| + | That doesn't comport very well, so far as I can tell, |
| + | with his customary reading of relative terms, suited |
| + | more to the multiplication of matrices "on the left". |
| + | |
| + | So I still have a few wrinkles to iron out before |
| + | I can give this story a smooth enough consistency. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 15=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | I have been planning for quite some time now to make my return to Peirce's |
| + | skyshaking "Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives" (1870), |
| + | and I can see that it's just about time to get down tuit, so let this |
| + | current bit of rambling inquiry function as the preamble to that. |
| + | All we need at the present, though, is a modus vivendi/operandi |
| + | for telling what is substantial from what is inessential in |
| + | the brook between symbolic conceits and dramatic actions |
| + | that we find afforded by means of the pragmatic maxim. |
| + | |
| + | Back to our "subinstance", the example in support of our first example. |
| + | I will now reconstruct it in a way that may prove to be less confusing. |
| + | |
| + | Let us make up the model universe $1$ = A + B + C and the 2-adic relation |
| + | n = "noder of", as when "X is a data record that contains a pointer to Y". |
| + | That interpretation is not important, it's just for the sake of intuition. |
| + | In general terms, the 2-adic relation n can be represented by this matrix: |
| + | |
| + | n = |
| + | |
| + | | n_AA (A:A) n_AB (A:B) n_AC (A:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | n_BA (B:A) n_BB (B:B) n_BC (B:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | n_CA (C:A) n_CB (C:B) n_CC (C:C) | |
| + | |
| + | Also, let n be such that |
| + | A is a noder of A and B, |
| + | B is a noder of B and C, |
| + | C is a noder of C and A. |
| + | |
| + | Filling in the instantial values of the "coefficients" n_ij, |
| + | as the indices i and j range over the universe of discourse: |
| + | |
| + | n = |
| + | |
| + | | 1 · (A:A) 1 · (A:B) 0 · (A:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 0 · (B:A) 1 · (B:B) 1 · (B:C) | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 1 · (C:A) 0 · (C:B) 1 · (C:C) | |
| + | |
| + | In Peirce's time, and even in some circles of mathematics today, |
| + | the information indicated by the elementary relatives (I:J), as |
| + | I, J range over the universe of discourse, would be referred to |
| + | as the "umbral elements" of the algebraic operation represented |
| + | by the matrix, though I seem to recall that Peirce preferred to |
| + | call these terms the "ingredients". When this ordered basis is |
| + | understood well enough, one will tend to drop any mention of it |
| + | from the matrix itself, leaving us nothing but these bare bones: |
| + | |
| + | n = |
| + | |
| + | | 1 1 0 | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 0 1 1 | |
| + | | | |
| + | | 1 0 1 | |
| + | |
| + | However the specification may come to be written, this |
| + | is all just convenient schematics for stipulating that: |
| + | |
| + | n = A:A + B:B + C:C + A:B + B:C + C:A |
| + | |
| + | Recognizing !1! = A:A + B:B + C:C to be the identity transformation, |
| + | the 2-adic relation n = "noder of" may be represented by an element |
| + | !1! + A:B + B:C + C:A of the so-called "group ring", all of which |
| + | just makes this element a special sort of linear transformation. |
| + | |
| + | Up to this point, we are still reading the elementary relatives of |
| + | the form I:J in the way that Peirce reads them in logical contexts: |
| + | I is the relate, J is the correlate, and in our current example we |
| + | read I:J, or more exactly, n_ij = 1, to say that I is a noder of J. |
| + | This is the mode of reading that we call "multiplying on the left". |
| + | |
| + | In the algebraic, permutational, or transformational contexts of |
| + | application, however, Peirce converts to the alternative mode of |
| + | reading, although still calling I the relate and J the correlate, |
| + | the elementary relative I:J now means that I gets changed into J. |
| + | In this scheme of reading, the transformation A:B + B:C + C:A is |
| + | a permutation of the aggregate $1$ = A + B + C, or what we would |
| + | now call the set {A, B, C}, in particular, it is the permutation |
| + | that is otherwise notated as: |
| + | |
| + | ( A B C ) |
| + | < > |
| + | ( B C A ) |
| + | |
| + | This is consistent with the convention that Peirce uses in |
| + | the paper "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324-327). |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 16=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | We have been contemplating the virtues and the utilities of |
| + | the pragmatic maxim as a hermeneutic heuristic, specifically, |
| + | as a principle of interpretation that guides us in finding a |
| + | clarifying representation for a problematic corpus of symbols |
| + | in terms of their actions on other symbols or their effects on |
| + | the syntactic contexts in which we conceive to distribute them. |
| + | I started off considering the regular representations of groups |
| + | as constituting what appears to be one of the simplest possible |
| + | applications of this overall principle of representation. |
| + | |
| + | There are a few problems of implementation that have to be worked out |
| + | in practice, most of which are cleared up by keeping in mind which of |
| + | several possible conventions we have chosen to follow at a given time. |
| + | But there does appear to remain this rather more substantial question: |
| + | |
| + | Are the effects we seek relates or correlates, or does it even matter? |
| + | |
| + | I will have to leave that question as it is for now, |
| + | in hopes that a solution will evolve itself in time. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 17=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | There a big reasons and little reasons for caring about this humble example. |
| + | The little reasons we find all under our feet. One big reason I can now |
| + | quite blazonly enounce in the fashion of this not so subtle subtitle: |
| + | |
| + | Obstacles to Applying the Pragmatic Maxim |
| + | |
| + | No sooner do you get a good idea and try to apply it |
| + | than you find that a motley array of obstacles arise. |
| + | |
| + | It seems as if I am constantly lamenting the fact these days that people, |
| + | and even admitted Peircean persons, do not in practice more consistently |
| + | apply the maxim of pragmatism to the purpose for which it is purportedly |
| + | intended by its author. That would be the clarification of concepts, or |
| + | intellectual symbols, to the point where their inherent senses, or their |
| + | lacks thereof, would be rendered manifest to all and sundry interpreters. |
| + | |
| + | There are big obstacles and little obstacles to applying the pragmatic maxim. |
| + | In good subgoaling fashion, I will merely mention a few of the bigger blocks, |
| + | as if in passing, and then get down to the devilish details that immediately |
| + | obstruct our way. |
| + | |
| + | Obstacle 1. People do not always read the instructions very carefully. |
| + | There is a tendency in readers of particular prior persuasions to blow |
| + | the problem all out of proportion, to think that the maxim is meant to |
| + | reveal the absolutely positive and the totally unique meaning of every |
| + | preconception to which they might deign or elect to apply it. Reading |
| + | the maxim with an even minimal attention, you can see that it promises |
| + | no such finality of unindexed sense, but ties what you conceive to you. |
| + | I have lately come to wonder at the tenacity of this misinterpretation. |
| + | Perhaps people reckon that nothing less would be worth their attention. |
| + | I am not sure. I can only say the achievement of more modest goals is |
| + | the sort of thing on which our daily life depends, and there can be no |
| + | final end to inquiry nor any ultimate community without a continuation |
| + | of life, and that means life on a day to day basis. All of which only |
| + | brings me back to the point of persisting with local meantime examples, |
| + | because if we can't apply the maxim there, we can't apply it anywhere. |
| + | |
| + | And now I need to go out of doors and weed my garden for a time ... |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 18=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | Obstacles to Applying the Pragmatic Maxim |
| + | |
| + | Obstacle 2. Applying the pragmatic maxim, even with a moderate aim, can be hard. |
| + | I think that my present example, deliberately impoverished as it is, affords us |
| + | with an embarassing richness of evidence of just how complex the simple can be. |
| + | |
| + | All the better reason for me to see if I can finish it up before moving on. |
| + | |
| + | Expressed most simply, the idea is to replace the question of "what it is", |
| + | which modest people know is far too difficult for them to answer right off, |
| + | with the question of "what it does", which most of us know a modicum about. |
| + | |
| + | In the case of regular representations of groups we found |
| + | a non-plussing surplus of answers to sort our way through. |
| + | So let us track back one more time to see if we can learn |
| + | any lessons that might carry over to more realistic cases. |
| + | |
| + | Here is is the operation table of V_4 once again: |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Klein Four-Group V_4 |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | · % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | e % e | f | g | h | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | f % f | e | h | g | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | g % g | h | e | f | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | | h % h | g | f | e | |
| + | | % | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | A group operation table is really just a device for |
| + | recording a certain 3-adic relation, to be specific, |
| + | the set of triples of the form <x, y, z> satisfying |
| + | the equation x·y = z where · is the group operation. |
| + | |
| + | In the case of V_4 = (G, ·), where G is the "underlying set" |
| + | {e, f, g, h}, we have the 3-adic relation L(V_4) c G x G x G |
| + | whose triples are listed below: |
| + | |
| + | | <e, e, e> |
| + | | <e, f, f> |
| + | | <e, g, g> |
| + | | <e, h, h> |
| + | | |
| + | | <f, e, f> |
| + | | <f, f, e> |
| + | | <f, g, h> |
| + | | <f, h, g> |
| + | | |
| + | | <g, e, g> |
| + | | <g, f, h> |
| + | | <g, g, e> |
| + | | <g, h, f> |
| + | | |
| + | | <h, e, h> |
| + | | <h, f, g> |
| + | | <h, g, f> |
| + | | <h, h, e> |
| + | |
| + | It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic |
| + | relation L c G^3 is actually a function L : G x G -> G. |
| + | It is from this functional perspective that we can see |
| + | an easy way to derive the two regular representations. |
| + | Since we have a function of the type L : G x G -> G, |
| + | we can define a couple of substitution operators: |
| + | |
| + | 1. Sub(x, <_, y>) puts any specified x into |
| + | the empty slot of the rheme <_, y>, with |
| + | the effect of producing the saturated |
| + | rheme <x, y> that evaluates to x·y. |
| + | |
| + | 2. Sub(x, <y, _>) puts any specified x into |
| + | the empty slot of the rheme <y, >, with |
| + | the effect of producing the saturated |
| + | rheme <y, x> that evaluates to y·x. |
| + | |
| + | In (1), we consider the effects of each x in its |
| + | practical bearing on contexts of the form <_, y>, |
| + | as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that |
| + | x takes <_, y> into x·y, for y in G, all of which |
| + | is summarily notated as x = {(y : x·y) : y in G}. |
| + | The pairs (y : x·y) can be found by picking an x |
| + | from the left margin of the group operation table |
| + | and considering its effects on each y in turn as |
| + | these run across the top margin. This aspect of |
| + | pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular |
| + | ante-representation: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | f = e:f + f:e + g:h + h:g |
| + | |
| + | g = e:g + f:h + g:e + h:f |
| + | |
| + | h = e:h + f:g + g:f + h:e |
| + | |
| + | In (2), we consider the effects of each x in its |
| + | practical bearing on contexts of the form <y, _>, |
| + | as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that |
| + | x takes <y, _> into y·x, for y in G, all of which |
| + | is summarily notated as x = {(y : y·x) : y in G}. |
| + | The pairs (y : y·x) can be found by picking an x |
| + | from the top margin of the group operation table |
| + | and considering its effects on each y in turn as |
| + | these run down the left margin. This aspect of |
| + | pragmatic definition we recognize as the regular |
| + | post-representation: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | f = e:f + f:e + g:h + h:g |
| + | |
| + | g = e:g + f:h + g:e + h:f |
| + | |
| + | h = e:h + f:g + g:f + h:e |
| + | |
| + | If the ante-rep looks the same as the post-rep, |
| + | now that I'm writing them in the same dialect, |
| + | that is because V_4 is abelian (commutative), |
| + | and so the two representations have the very |
| + | same effects on each point of their bearing. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 19=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | So long as we're in the neighborhood, we might as well take in |
| + | some more of the sights, for instance, the smallest example of |
| + | a non-abelian (non-commutative) group. This is a group of six |
| + | elements, say, G = {e, f, g, h, i, j}, with no relation to any |
| + | other employment of these six symbols being implied, of course, |
| + | and it can most easily be represented as the permutation group |
| + | on a set of three letters, say, X = {A, B, C}, usually notated |
| + | as G = Sym(X) or more abstractly and briefly, as Sym(3) or S_3. |
| + | Here are the permutation (= substitution) operations in Sym(X): |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Permutations or Substitutions in Sym_{A, B, C} |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | e | f | g | h | i | j | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |
| + | | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | C A B | B C A | A C B | C B A | B A C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | Here is the operation table for S_3, given in abstract fashion: |
| + | |
| + | Table 2. Symmetric Group S_3 |
| + | |
| + | | ^ |
| + | | e / \ e |
| + | | / \ |
| + | | / e \ |
| + | | f / \ / \ f |
| + | | / \ / \ |
| + | | / f \ f \ |
| + | | g / \ / \ / \ g |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / g \ g \ g \ |
| + | | h / \ / \ / \ / \ h |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / h \ e \ e \ h \ |
| + | | i / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ i |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / i \ i \ f \ j \ i \ |
| + | | j / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ j |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | ( j \ j \ j \ i \ h \ j ) |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ h \ h \ e \ j \ i / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ i \ g \ f \ h / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ f \ e \ g / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ g \ f / |
| + | | \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / |
| + | | \ e / |
| + | | \ / |
| + | | \ / |
| + | | v |
| + | |
| + | By the way, we will meet with the symmetric group S_3 again |
| + | when we return to take up the study of Peirce's early paper |
| + | "On a Class of Multiple Algebras" (CP 3.324-327), and also |
| + | his late unpublished work "The Simplest Mathematics" (1902) |
| + | (CP 4.227-323), with particular reference to the section |
| + | that treats of "Trichotomic Mathematics" (CP 4.307-323). |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 20=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | By way of collecting a short-term pay-off for all the work -- |
| + | not to mention the peirce-spiration -- that we sweated out |
| + | over the regular representations of the Klein 4-group V_4, |
| + | let us write out as quickly as possible in "relative form" |
| + | a minimal budget of representations of the symmetric group |
| + | on three letters, S_3 = Sym(3). After doing the usual bit |
| + | of compare and contrast among these divers representations, |
| + | we will have enough concrete material beneath our abstract |
| + | belts to tackle a few of the presently obscur'd details of |
| + | Peirce's early "Algebra + Logic" papers. |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Permutations or Substitutions in Sym {A, B, C} |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | e | f | g | h | i | j | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |
| + | | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | C A B | B C A | A C B | C B A | B A C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | Writing this table in relative form generates |
| + | the following "natural representation" of S_3. |
| + | |
| + | e = A:A + B:B + C:C |
| + | |
| + | f = A:C + B:A + C:B |
| + | |
| + | g = A:B + B:C + C:A |
| + | |
| + | h = A:A + B:C + C:B |
| + | |
| + | i = A:C + B:B + C:A |
| + | |
| + | j = A:B + B:A + C:C |
| + | |
| + | I have without stopping to think about it written out this natural |
| + | representation of S_3 in the style that comes most naturally to me, |
| + | to wit, the "right" way, whereby an ordered pair configured as X:Y |
| + | constitutes the turning of X into Y. It is possible that the next |
| + | time we check in with CSP that we will have to adjust our sense of |
| + | direction, but that will be an easy enough bridge to cross when we |
| + | come to it. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 21=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Consider what effects that might 'conceivably' |
| + | | have practical bearings you 'conceive' the |
| + | | objects of your 'conception' to have. Then, |
| + | | your 'conception' of those effects is the |
| + | | whole of your 'conception' of the object. |
| + | | |
| + | | Charles Sanders Peirce, |
| + | | "Maxim of Pragmaticism", CP 5.438. |
| + | |
| + | To construct the regular representations of S_3, |
| + | we pick up from the data of its operation table: |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Symmetric Group S_3 |
| + | |
| + | | ^ |
| + | | e / \ e |
| + | | / \ |
| + | | / e \ |
| + | | f / \ / \ f |
| + | | / \ / \ |
| + | | / f \ f \ |
| + | | g / \ / \ / \ g |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / g \ g \ g \ |
| + | | h / \ / \ / \ / \ h |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / h \ e \ e \ h \ |
| + | | i / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ i |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | / i \ i \ f \ j \ i \ |
| + | | j / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ j |
| + | | / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ |
| + | | ( j \ j \ j \ i \ h \ j ) |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ h \ h \ e \ j \ i / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ i \ g \ f \ h / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ f \ e \ g / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / \ / |
| + | | \ g \ f / |
| + | | \ / \ / |
| + | | \ / \ / |
| + | | \ e / |
| + | | \ / |
| + | | \ / |
| + | | v |
| + | |
| + | Just by way of staying clear about what we are doing, |
| + | let's return to the recipe that we worked out before: |
| + | |
| + | It is part of the definition of a group that the 3-adic |
| + | relation L c G^3 is actually a function L : G x G -> G. |
| + | It is from this functional perspective that we can see |
| + | an easy way to derive the two regular representations. |
| + | |
| + | Since we have a function of the type L : G x G -> G, |
| + | we can define a couple of substitution operators: |
| + | |
| + | 1. Sub(x, <_, y>) puts any specified x into |
| + | the empty slot of the rheme <_, y>, with |
| + | the effect of producing the saturated |
| + | rheme <x, y> that evaluates to x·y. |
| + | |
| + | 2. Sub(x, <y, _>) puts any specified x into |
| + | the empty slot of the rheme <y, >, with |
| + | the effect of producing the saturated |
| + | rheme <y, x> that evaluates to y·x. |
| + | |
| + | In (1), we consider the effects of each x in its |
| + | practical bearing on contexts of the form <_, y>, |
| + | as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that |
| + | x takes <_, y> into x·y, for y in G, all of which |
| + | is summarily notated as x = {(y : x·y) : y in G}. |
| + | The pairs (y : x·y) can be found by picking an x |
| + | from the left margin of the group operation table |
| + | and considering its effects on each y in turn as |
| + | these run along the right margin. This produces |
| + | the regular ante-representation of S_3, like so: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h + i:i + j:j |
| + | |
| + | f = e:f + f:g + g:e + h:j + i:h + j:i |
| + | |
| + | g = e:g + f:e + g:f + h:i + i:j + j:h |
| + | |
| + | h = e:h + f:i + g:j + h:e + i:f + j:g |
| + | |
| + | i = e:i + f:j + g:h + h:g + i:e + j:f |
| + | |
| + | j = e:j + f:h + g:i + h:f + i:g + j:e |
| + | |
| + | In (2), we consider the effects of each x in its |
| + | practical bearing on contexts of the form <y, _>, |
| + | as y ranges over G, and the effects are such that |
| + | x takes <y, _> into y·x, for y in G, all of which |
| + | is summarily notated as x = {(y : y·x) : y in G}. |
| + | The pairs (y : y·x) can be found by picking an x |
| + | on the right margin of the group operation table |
| + | and considering its effects on each y in turn as |
| + | these run along the left margin. This generates |
| + | the regular post-representation of S_3, like so: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h + i:i + j:j |
| + | |
| + | f = e:f + f:g + g:e + h:i + i:j + j:h |
| + | |
| + | g = e:g + f:e + g:f + h:j + i:h + j:i |
| + | |
| + | h = e:h + f:j + g:i + h:e + i:g + j:f |
| + | |
| + | i = e:i + f:h + g:j + h:f + i:e + j:g |
| + | |
| + | j = e:j + f:i + g:h + h:g + i:f + j:e |
| + | |
| + | If the ante-rep looks different from the post-rep, |
| + | it is just as it should be, as S_3 is non-abelian |
| + | (non-commutative), and so the two representations |
| + | differ in the details of their practical effects, |
| + | though, of course, being representations of the |
| + | same abstract group, they must be isomorphic. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 22=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | the way of heaven and earth |
| + | | is to be long continued |
| + | | in their operation |
| + | | without stopping |
| + | | |
| + | | i ching, hexagram 32 |
| + | |
| + | You may be wondering what happened to the announced subject |
| + | of "Differential Logic", and if you think that we have been |
| + | taking a slight "excursion" -- to use my favorite euphemism |
| + | for "digression" -- my reply to the charge of a scenic rout |
| + | would need to be both "yes and no". What happened was this. |
| + | At the sign-post marked by Sigil 7, we made the observation |
| + | that the shift operators E_ij form a transformation group |
| + | that acts on the propositions of the form f : B^2 -> B. |
| + | Now group theory is a very attractive subject, but it |
| + | did not really have the effect of drawing us so far |
| + | off our initial course as you may at first think. |
| + | For one thing, groups, in particular, the groups |
| + | that have come to be named after the Norwegian |
| + | mathematician Marius Sophus Lie, have turned |
| + | out to be of critical utility in the solution |
| + | of differential equations. For another thing, |
| + | group operations afford us examples of triadic |
| + | relations that have been extremely well-studied |
| + | over the years, and this provides us with quite |
| + | a bit of guidance in the study of sign relations, |
| + | another class of triadic relations of significance |
| + | for logical studies, in our brief acquaintance with |
| + | which we have scarcely even started to break the ice. |
| + | Finally, I could hardly avoid taking up the connection |
| + | between group representations, a very generic class of |
| + | logical models, and the all-important pragmatic maxim. |
| + | |
| + | Biographical Data for Marius Sophus Lie (1842-1899): |
| + | |
| + | http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Lie.html |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 23=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | Bein' on the twenty-third of June, |
| + | | As I sat weaving all at my loom, |
| + | | Bein' on the twenty-third of June, |
| + | | As I sat weaving all at my loom, |
| + | | I heard a thrush, singing on yon bush, |
| + | | And the song she sang was The Jug of Punch. |
| + | |
| + | We've seen a couple of groups, V_4 and S_3, represented in various ways, and |
| + | we've seen their representations presented in a variety of different manners. |
| + | Let us look at one other stylistic variant for presenting a representation |
| + | that is frequently seen, the so-called "matrix representation" of a group. |
| + | |
| + | Recalling the manner of our acquaintance with the symmetric group S_3, |
| + | we began with the "bigraph" (bipartite graph) picture of its natural |
| + | representation as the set of all permutations or substitutions on |
| + | the set X = {A, B, C}. |
| + | |
| + | Table 1. Permutations or Substitutions in Sym {A, B, C} |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | e | f | g | h | i | j | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | A B C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |
| + | | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | v v v | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | A B C | C A B | B C A | A C B | C B A | B A C | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | Then we rewrote these permutations -- being functions f : X --> X |
| + | they can also be recognized as being 2-adic relations f c X x X -- |
| + | in "relative form", in effect, in the manner to which Peirce would |
| + | have made us accostumed had he been given a relative half-a-chance: |
| + | |
| + | e = A:A + B:B + C:C |
| + | |
| + | f = A:C + B:A + C:B |
| + | |
| + | g = A:B + B:C + C:A |
| + | |
| + | h = A:A + B:C + C:B |
| + | |
| + | i = A:C + B:B + C:A |
| + | |
| + | j = A:B + B:A + C:C |
| + | |
| + | These days one is much more likely to encounter the natural representation |
| + | of S_3 in the form of a "linear representation", that is, as a family of |
| + | linear transformations that map the elements of a suitable vector space |
| + | into each other, all of which would in turn usually be represented by |
| + | a set of matrices like these: |
| + | |
| + | Table 2. Matrix Representations of Permutations in Sym(3) |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | e | f | g | h | i | j | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o=========o |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | |
| + | | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | |
| + | | 0 0 1 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 1 0 | 1 0 0 | 0 0 1 | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o---------o |
| + | |
| + | The key to the mysteries of these matrices is revealed by noting that their |
| + | coefficient entries are arrayed and overlayed on a place mat marked like so: |
| + | |
| + | | A:A A:B A:C | |
| + | | B:A B:B B:C | |
| + | | C:A C:B C:C | |
| + | |
| + | Of course, the place-settings of convenience at different symposia may vary. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 24=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | In the beginning was the three-pointed star, |
| + | | One smile of light across the empty face; |
| + | | One bough of bone across the rooting air, |
| + | | The substance forked that marrowed the first sun; |
| + | | And, burning ciphers on the round of space, |
| + | | Heaven and hell mixed as they spun. |
| + | | |
| + | | Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 1 |
| + | |
| + | I'm afrayed that this thread is just bound to keep |
| + | encountering its manifold of tensuous distractions, |
| + | but I'd like to try and return now to the topic of |
| + | inquiry, espectrally viewed in differential aspect. |
| + | |
| + | Here's one picture of how it begins, |
| + | one angle on the point of departure: |
| + | |
| + | o-----------------------------------------------------------o |
| + | | | |
| + | | | |
| + | | o-------------o | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | / \ | |
| + | | o o | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | Observation | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | | | | |
| + | | o--o----------o o----------o--o | |
| + | | / \ \ / / \ | |
| + | | / \ d_I ^ o ^ d_E / \ | |
| + | | / \ \/ \/ / \ | |
| + | | / \ /\ /\ / \ | |
| + | | / \ / @ \ / \ | |
| + | | o o--o---|---o--o o | |
| + | | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | v | | | |
| + | | | Expectation | d_O | Intention | | |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | | | | | | | |
| + | | o o o o | |
| + | | \ \ / / | |
| + | | \ \ / / | |
| + | | \ \ / / | |
| + | | \ o / | |
| + | | \ / \ / | |
| + | | o-------------o o-------------o | |
| + | | | |
| + | | | |
| + | o-----------------------------------------------------------o |
| + | |
| + | From what we must assume was a state of "Unconscious Nirvana" (UN), |
| + | since we do not acutely become conscious until after we are exiled |
| + | from that garden of our blissful innocence, where our Expectations, |
| + | our Intentions, our Observations all subsist in a state of perfect |
| + | harmony, one with every barely perceived other, something intrudes |
| + | on that scene of paradise to knock us out of that blessed isle and |
| + | to trouble our countenance forever after at the retrospect thereof. |
| + | |
| + | The least disturbance, it being provident and prudent both to take |
| + | that first up, will arise in just one of three ways, in accord with |
| + | the mode of discord that importunes on our equanimity, whether it is |
| + | Expectation, Intention, Observation that incipiently incites the riot, |
| + | departing as it will from congruence with the other two modes of being. |
| + | |
| + | In short, we cross just one of the three lines that border on the center, |
| + | or perhaps it is better to say that the objective situation transits one |
| + | of the chordal bounds of harmony, for the moment marked as d_E, d_I, d_O |
| + | to note the fact one's Expectation, Intention, Observation, respectively, |
| + | is the mode that we duly indite as the one that's sounding the sour note. |
| + | |
| + | A difference between Expectation and Observation is experienced |
| + | as a "Surprise", a phenomenon that cries out for an Explanation. |
| + | |
| + | A discrepancy between Intention and Observation is experienced |
| + | as a "Problem", of the species that calls for a Plan of Action. |
| + | |
| + | I can remember that I once thought up what I thought up an apt |
| + | name for a gap between Expectation and Intention, but I cannot |
| + | recall what it was, nor yet find the notes where I recorded it. |
| + | |
| + | At any rate, the modes of experiencing a surprising phenomenon |
| + | or a problematic situation, as described just now, are already |
| + | complex modalities, and will need to be analyzed further if we |
| + | want to relate them to the minimal changes d_E, d_I, d_O. Let |
| + | me think about that for a little while and see what transpires. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 25=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | In the beginning was the pale signature, |
| + | | Three-syllabled and starry as the smile; |
| + | | And after came the imprints on the water, |
| + | | Stamp of the minted face upon the moon; |
| + | | The blood that touched the crosstree and the grail |
| + | | Touched the first cloud and left a sign. |
| + | | |
| + | | Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 2 |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Note 26=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | | In the beginning was the mounting fire |
| + | | That set alight the weathers from a spark, |
| + | | A three-eyed, red-eyed spark, blunt as a flower; |
| + | | Life rose and spouted from the rolling seas, |
| + | | Burst in the roots, pumped from the earth and rock |
| + | | The secret oils that drive the grass. |
| + | | |
| + | | Dylan Thomas, "In The Beginning", Verse 3 |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ==Differential Logic 2002 • Work Area== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | problem about writing: |
| + | |
| + | e = e:e + f:f + g:g + h:h |
| + | |
| + | no recursion intended |
| + | need for a work-around |
| + | ways of explaining away |
| + | |
| + | action on signs not objects |
| + | |
| + | mathematical definition of representation |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ==Differential Logic 2002 • Discussion== |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Discussion Note 1=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | BU = Benjamin Udell |
| + | |
| + | BU: Your exposition of differential logic is over my head, YET -- |
| + | |
| + | Apologies to all for posting so many notes at once, |
| + | but I've found that it's best to break this stuff |
| + | up into easy pieces, and I wanted to get to the |
| + | part about the pragmatic maxim before everyone |
| + | lapsed into a coma. Too late, most likely. |
| + | |
| + | I just thought that it was about time that I supply a concrete example |
| + | in support of all those wild claims I've been making about how crucial |
| + | Peirce's mathematical way of looking at logic is to the future of both |
| + | subjects. From my perspective, his logic is not some museum curiosity, |
| + | but a living force and a working tool, a resource whose full potential |
| + | is yet to be fully explored. By way of illustrating the power of this |
| + | approach, I will exposit here the subject of differential logic along |
| + | lines that a slight extension of Peirce's Alpha Graphs makes possible. |
| + | The basic idea of differential logic was hinted at by Leibniz, exists |
| + | in explicit form as far back as the Boole-DeMorgan correspondence, it |
| + | was familiar to Babbage, and is well-known to circuit engineers today, |
| + | but its full development has been hobbled by the recalcitrant calculus |
| + | with which today's logic teachers still shackle today's logic students. |
| + | |
| + | BU: I'm wondering whether you could do me (or maybe a few of us) the |
| + | favor of temporarily morphing into E.T. Bell & explaining to a |
| + | mathematically ill educated person like me, what differential |
| + | logic involves. (E.g., does this have something to do with |
| + | 1st- vs. 2nd-order logic?) I also mean analogously as in |
| + | the following examples: |
| + | |
| + | Oh gee, could I play John Taine instead? |
| + | Bell was a bit notorious for tailoring |
| + | the facts as befit the better story. |
| + | |
| + | We are building the differential extension of "Zeroth Order Logic" (ZOL), |
| + | that is to say, starting with propositional calculus or sentential logic. |
| + | |
| + | BU: Ex.: Measure theory is used for probability theory. The basic thing is |
| + | to find the relative sizes of different portions of the area under the |
| + | curve (the total area is usually set at unity). (If I've got that right!) |
| + | This is finding the definite integrals representing the portions. |
| + | (Actually I've probably got this wrong.) |
| + | |
| + | This is square measure theory in a venn diagram world. |
| + | You may find it useful to stroll through this gallery: |
| + | |
| + | http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg03585.html |
| + | |
| + | BU: Ex.: In optimization sometimes one looks for the minimum or maximum |
| + | of a curve. This amounts to finding the point(s) of the curve where |
| + | the slope is zero. Sometimes one wants to find the intersections of |
| + | various curves; in any case sometimes one seeks to find points on |
| + | curves, points which have certain specified properties in terms |
| + | of the curve, such as being a minimum, a maximum, a point of |
| + | intersection, etc. |
| + | |
| + | The slope is a derivative, df/dx, which is a number in the relevant field, |
| + | being the coefficient that sits next to the differential factor dx in the |
| + | appropriate differential expansion. It turns out to be a bit more useful |
| + | to preserve the whole differential term. Since our field is B = GF(2), |
| + | the derivative is either 0 or 1, so the term dx is either there or not. |
| + | |
| + | BU: I do see you mentioning finding of differentials, but I don't know |
| + | whether that's the basic point. Also, I'm a little confused in my |
| + | ignorance, since I thought that if you're talking about discrete |
| + | objects (statements), you'd be talking about differences rather |
| + | than differentials. In any case I'm not sure how to think about |
| + | a differential or a difference between two statements. |
| + | |
| + | We are starting with the logical analogue of "finite difference calculus", |
| + | and will work up to the logical analogue of true differentials bit by bit. |
| + | |
| + | The definition that you want to keep in mind is the concept of |
| + | a differential as a locally linear approximation to a function. |
| + | This is a notion that can very often make sense even when all |
| + | of the familiar formulas for it fail to carry over by means |
| + | of the usual brands of automatic analogues. |
| + | |
| + | Think of a proposition, a shaded region in a venn diagram, |
| + | as if the shaded region were a mesa of height 1, and view |
| + | that as a potential function or a probability density on |
| + | the universe of discourse. Then think about gradients. |
| + | |
| + | To be continuous --- |
| + | If not exactly |
| + | Uniformly ... |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Discussion Note 2=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | BU = Benjamin Udell |
| + | JA = Jon Awbrey |
| + | |
| + | BU: I found this at Semeion, Research Center of Sciences of Communication: |
| + | |
| + | http://www.semeion.it/GLOSSTH1.htm |
| + | |
| + | | Differential Logic: is a different logic to build up |
| + | | complex systems. Its inspiration is biology. According |
| + | | to the differential logic, a unit develops dividing itself |
| + | | into more units and, in doing so, radically changes the state |
| + | | of its information. This logic is not tautological, because |
| + | | during the process the systems increases its quantity of |
| + | | organization. |
| + | |
| + | | Differential System: is a system whose development happens in the same |
| + | | way as biological systems; that is, through differentiation of its units. |
| + | |
| + | BU: Is this the same differential logic that you're talking about? |
| + | |
| + | I think that they are speaking of "differentiation" in the sense |
| + | of embryology or developmental biology. That happens to be a big |
| + | interest of mine in a remotely related way -- the data structures, |
| + | one of whose alternate nicknames is "conifers", that I use in my |
| + | "learning and reasoning" program, were partly influenced by the |
| + | way that so-called "growth cones" ramify throughout the nervous |
| + | system in the development of neural tissue during neurogenesis |
| + | and epigenetic learning. Other than that, there's no terribly |
| + | close conscious connection with what I'm doing with diff log |
| + | at the moment. |
| + | |
| + | JA: We are building the differential extension of "Zeroth Order Logic" (ZOL), |
| + | that is to say, starting with propositional calculus or sentential logic. |
| + | |
| + | BU: Ex.: Measure theory is used for probability theory. |
| + | The basic thing is to find the relative sizes of |
| + | different portions of the area under the curve |
| + | (the total area is usually set at unity). |
| + | (If I've got that right!) This is finding |
| + | the definite integrals representing the |
| + | portions. (Actually I've probably got |
| + | this wrong.) |
| + | |
| + | JA: This is square measure theory in a venn diagram world. |
| + | You may find it useful to stroll through this gallery: |
| + | |
| + | JA: http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg03585.html |
| + | |
| + | BU: If it's square measure theory, ultimately the interest will be |
| + | in some kind of logical analog of mathematical integration? |
| + | |
| + | I just mean that propositions are (modeled as, regarded as) step-functions, |
| + | functions having the form f : X -> B, where X is the universe of discourse |
| + | and B = {0, 1}. If B is regarded as a "field", a space with some analogue |
| + | of the usual four functions (add, subtract, multiply, divide), then it is |
| + | called the "galois field of order 2" and notated as GF(2). In set theory |
| + | these are called "characteristic functions" and in statistics they are |
| + | known as "indicator functions" because they characterize or indicate |
| + | the subset of X where f evaluates to 1. This subset is the inverse |
| + | image of 1 under f, horribly notated in Asciiland as f^(-1)(1) c X, |
| + | and various other folks call it the "antecedent", the "fiber", or |
| + | the "pre-image" of 1 under f. I tend to use the "fiber" language, |
| + | and also make use of the "fiber bars" [|...|] that allow of the |
| + | more succinct form [| f |] = f^(-1)(1) = {x in X : f(x) = 1}. |
| + | |
| + | B |
| + | ^ |
| + | 1 + ****** *********** |
| + | | * * * * |
| + | | * * * * |
| + | 0 o*****----******---------***********> X |
| + | |
| + | BU: Ex.: In optimization sometimes one looks for the minimum or maximum of |
| + | a curve. This amounts to finding the point(s) of the curve where the |
| + | slope is zero. Sometimes one wants to find the intersections of various |
| + | curves; in any case sometimes one seeks to find points on curves, points |
| + | which have certain specified properties in terms of the curve, such as being |
| + | a minimum, a maximum, a point of intersection, etc. |
| + | |
| + | In mathematics one tends to take spaces and the functions on spaces in tandem, |
| + | considering ordered pairs like (X, X -> K), where X is the space of interest, |
| + | K is a space with a special relation to X, typically its "field of scalars", |
| + | and (X -> K) is the set of all pertinent functions from X to K. |
| + | |
| + | In differential logic, we try to exploit what analogies |
| + | we can find between real settings like (X, X -> R) and |
| + | boolean settings like (Y, Y -> B), where R is the set |
| + | of real numbers and B = {0, 1}. At the entry level |
| + | of generality, standard tricks of the trade permit |
| + | us to "coordinate" X as a k-dimensional real space |
| + | R^k and Y as a k-dimensional boolean space B^k, |
| + | and so we begin by cranking the analogy mill |
| + | forth and back between (R^k, R^k -> R) and |
| + | (B^k, B^k -> B). |
| + | |
| + | Starting to nod off ... |
| + | will have to get to |
| + | the rest tomorrow. |
| + | |
| + | JA: The slope is a derivative, df/dx, which is a number in the relevant field, |
| + | being the coefficient that sits next to the differential factor dx in the |
| + | appropriate differential expansion. It turns out to be a bit more useful |
| + | to preserve the whole differential term. Since our field is B = GF(2), |
| + | the derivative is either 0 or 1, so the term dx is either there or not. |
| + | |
| + | BU: Huh? |
| + | |
| + | BU: I do see you mentioning finding of differentials, |
| + | but I don't know whether that's the basic point. |
| + | Also, I'm a little confused in my ignorance, |
| + | since I thought that if you're talking about |
| + | discrete objects (statements), you'd be talking |
| + | about differences rather than differentials. |
| + | In any case I'm not sure how to think about |
| + | a differential or a difference between two |
| + | statements. |
| + | |
| + | JA: We are starting with the logical analogue of "finite difference calculus", |
| + | and will work up to the logical analogue of true differentials bit by bit. |
| + | |
| + | JA: The definition that you want to keep in mind is the concept of |
| + | a differential as a locally linear approximation to a function. |
| + | This is a notion that can very often makes sense even when all |
| + | of the familiar formulas for it fail to carry over by means of |
| + | the usual brands of automatic analogues. |
| + | |
| + | JA: Think of a proposition, a shaded region in a venn diagram, |
| + | as if the shaded region were a mesa of height 1, and view |
| + | that as a potential function or a probability density on |
| + | the universe of discourse. Then think about gradients. |
| + | |
| + | BU: potential function? gradients? |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ===Diff Log 2002 • Discussion Note 3=== |
| + | |
| + | <pre> |
| + | |
| + | IS = Inna Semetsky |
| + | JA = Jon Awbrey |
| + | |
| + | IS: You mentioned circuit engineers in one of your posts. Computer technology |
| + | is based on designing circuits aiming at information processing. With this |
| + | in mind, how then Peirce's philosophy differ from the so called computational |
| + | brand of contemporary cognitive science who equate "mind" with the information |
| + | processing device, and posit that there is nothing else to it. |
| + | |
| + | That discussion was rendered a hopeless muddle by the fact that |
| + | cognitive science folks never read anything beyond a ten-year |
| + | window on their own literature, if that much, and so they |
| + | fell into using the term "functionalism" in a way that |
| + | was almost exactly the opposite of the way that it |
| + | had always been used before. |
| + | |
| + | At any rate, the interesting part of the Whole Idea |
| + | goes back to Aristotle's dictum that "soul is form", |
| + | In that form it might be something worth discussing. |
| + | |
| + | IS: Indeed difference may be considered as an "error" |
| + | between input and output, and manipulated upon by |
| + | further differentiations to feed into "the process" |
| + | again and again. I was very impressed with your posts |
| + | on differential logic (I admit that I just skimmed them) |
| + | but couldn't help thinking that all this "and", "or", |
| + | "if ... then", and other functions of Boolean algebra |
| + | indeed can be, and are being, constructed electronically. |
| + | Yet I would hate to think that what cognitivists are doing -- |
| + | even unknowingly -- is employing Peirce's semiotics. They |
| + | use Boolean logic alright. Is it all that is there in Peirce? |
| + | |
| + | There is a differential aspect to inquiry. Inquiry begins with uncertainty, |
| + | a condition of high cognitive entropy, if you will. Differences generalize |
| + | to distributions. The more uniform the distribution the higher the entropy. |
| + | Uncertainties are commonly associated with several categories of difference: |
| + | |
| + | 1. A difference between expectation and observation is called a "surprise". |
| + | 2. A difference between intention and observation is called a "problem". |
| + | 3. A difference between expectation and intention is called a (I forget). |
| + | |
| + | The cybernetic notion of an error-controlled regulator is a special case of this. |
| + | These are some of the main reasons that I thought a differential logic was needed. |
| + | |
| + | IS: While on the subject: I mentioned not once that part of my research is a |
| + | peculiar connection between Deleuze philosophy and american pragmatism, |
| + | not the least of which is the notion of difference. Deleuze has been |
| + | designated as "difference engineer" and his major opus is called |
| + | "Difference and Repetition". |
| + | |
| + | Five or six years ago, while taking a bit of a break from my normal routine, |
| + | I'd started on a collection of readings along these very lines, mostly just |
| + | picking them out by free association: Deleuze, 'Difference and Repetition', |
| + | 'The Fold'; Derrida, 'Writing and Difference'; Lyotard, 'The Differend'; |
| + | Giroux, 'Border Crossings', and so on. But I have no really clear sense of |
| + | what it was all about any more. A lot of this writing always strikes me as |
| + | very insightful and intuitive, while I am reading it, and then the next one |
| + | says something radically different, that also strikes me as very insightful |
| + | and intuitive, so after a while I tend to become just a little indifferent. |
| + | But I see that I have long passages marked in the margins of the 'The Fold', |
| + | so perhaps the Leibniz link is something that I will have recourse to again. |
| + | Of course, 'Timaeus' and Kierkegaard 'On Repetition' are eternal favorites. |
| + | |
| + | </pre> |
| + | |
| + | ==Differential Logic 2002 • Document History== |
| + | |
| + | * http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002240/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/thrd28.html#04040 |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20140406040004/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04040.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001949/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04041.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010502/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04045.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005212/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04046.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001954/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04047.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010620/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04048.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010550/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04052.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010724/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04054.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000847/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04055.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001959/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04067.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010507/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04068.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002014/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04069.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010701/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04070.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612003540/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04072.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005229/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04073.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110610153117/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04074.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010555/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04077.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612001918/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04079.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005244/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04080.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612005249/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04268.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010626/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04269.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612000853/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04272.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612010514/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04273.html |
| + | # http://web.archive.org/web/20110612002235/http://suo.ieee.org/ontology/msg04290.html |